Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Minds, machines and Turing: The indistinguishability of indistinguishables.Stevan Harnad - 2000 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 9 (4):425-445.
    Turing's celebrated 1950 paper proposes a very general methodological criterion for modelling mental function: total functional equivalence and indistinguishability. His criterion gives rise to a hierarchy of Turing Tests, from subtotal ("toy") fragments of our functions (t1), to total symbolic (pen-pal) function (T2 -- the standard Turing Test), to total external sensorimotor (robotic) function (T3), to total internal microfunction (T4), to total indistinguishability in every empirically discernible respect (T5). This is a "reverse-engineering" hierarchy of (decreasing) empirical underdetermination of the theory (...)
    Direct download (17 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • First-person current.Paul L. Harris - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):48-49.
  • Faulting ambition: A double standard?Henry Harpending - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):78-78.
  • Computational commitment and physical realization.Robert M. Harrish - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):408-409.
  • A Critique of Top‐down Independent Levels Models of Speech Production: Evidence from Non‐plan‐Internal Speech Errors.Trevor A. Harley - 1984 - Cognitive Science 8 (3):191-219.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Images, memory, and perception.Alastair Hannay - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):552-553.
  • Experiment and reality.Mark Hallett - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):219-219.
  • The many uses of 'belief' in AI.Robert F. Hadley - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (1):55-74.
    Within AI and the cognitively related disciplines, there exist a multiplicity of uses of belief. On the face of it, these differing uses reflect differing views about the nature of an objective phenomenon called belief. In this paper I distinguish six distinct ways in which belief is used in AI. I shall argue that not all these uses reflect a difference of opinion about an objective feature of reality. Rather, in some cases, the differing uses reflect differing concerns with special (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • When is a picture worth so many words?Ralph Norman Haber - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):147-148.
  • Language training versus training in relations.Lyn Haber - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):146-147.
  • Eidetic imagery, monocularity, and computational models of vision.Ralph Norman Haber - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):297-298.
  • Visual perception is underdetermined by stimulation.John W. Gyr - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):386-386.
  • Know my own mind? I should be so lucky!Jennifer M. Gurd & John C. Marshall - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):47-48.
  • Paranoia concerning program-resistant aspects of the mind - and let's drop rocks on Turing's toes again.Keith Gunderson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):537-539.
  • On behalf of phenomenological parity for the attitudes.Keith Gunderson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):46-47.
  • Components versus factors.J. P. Guilford - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):591-592.
  • Real Sparks of Artificial Intelligence and the Importance of Inner Interpretability.Alex Grzankowski - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    The present paper looks at one of the most thorough articles on the intelligence of GPT, research conducted by engineers at Microsoft. Although there is a great deal of value in their work, I will argue that, for familiar philosophical reasons, their methodology, ‘Black-box Interpretability’ is wrongheaded. But there is a better way. There is an exciting and emerging discipline of ‘Inner Interpretability’ (also sometimes called ‘White-box Interpretability’) that aims to uncover the internal activations and weights of models in order (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The microscopic analysis of behavior: Toward a synthesis of instrumental, perceptual, and cognitive ideas.Stephen Grossberg - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):594-595.
  • Direct perception or adaptive resonance?Stephen Grossberg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):385-386.
  • Turing’s Biological Philosophy: Morphogenesis, Mechanisms and Organicism.Hajo Greif, Adam Kubiak & Paweł Stacewicz - 2023 - Philosophies 8 (1):8.
    Alan M. Turing’s last published work and some posthumously published manuscripts were dedicated to the development of his theory of organic pattern formation. In “The Chemical Basis of Morphogenesis” (1952), he provided an elaborated mathematical formulation of the theory of the origins of biological form that had been first proposed by Sir D’Arcy Wendworth Thompson in On Growth and Form (1917/1942). While arguably his most mathematically detailed and his systematically most ambitious effort, Turing’s morphogenetical writings also form the most thematically (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental models: Rationality, representation and process.D. W. Green - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):352-353.
  • Exploring Minds: Modes of Modeling and Simulation in Artificial Intelligence.Hajo Greif - 2021 - Perspectives on Science 29 (4):409-435.
    The aim of this paper is to grasp the relevant distinctions between various ways in which models and simulations in Artificial Intelligence (AI) relate to cognitive phenomena. In order to get a systematic picture, a taxonomy is developed that is based on the coordinates of formal versus material analogies and theory-guided versus pre-theoretic models in science. These distinctions have parallels in the computational versus mimetic aspects and in analytic versus exploratory types of computer simulation. The proposed taxonomy cuts across the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Exploring Minds: Modes of Modelling and Simulation in Artificial Intelligence.Hajo Greif - 2021 - Perspectives on Science 29 (4):409-435.
    -/- The aim of this paper is to grasp the relevant distinctions between various ways in which models and simulations in Artificial Intelligence (AI) relate to cognitive phenomena. In order to get a systematic picture, a taxonomy is developed that is based on the coordinates of formal versus material analogies and theory-guided versus pre-theoretic models in science. These distinctions have parallels in the computational versus mimetic aspects and in analytic versus exploratory types of computer simulation. The proposed taxonomy cuts across (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Analogue Models and Universal Machines. Paradigms of Epistemic Transparency in Artificial Intelligence.Hajo Greif - 2022 - Minds and Machines 32 (1):111-133.
    The problem of epistemic opacity in Artificial Intelligence is often characterised as a problem of intransparent algorithms that give rise to intransparent models. However, the degrees of transparency of an AI model should not be taken as an absolute measure of the properties of its algorithms but of the model’s degree of intelligibility to human users. Its epistemically relevant elements are to be specified on various levels above and beyond the computational one. In order to elucidate this claim, I first (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The contents of consciousness: A neuropsychological conjecture.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):659-76.
    Drawing on previous models of anxiety, intermediate memory, the positive symptoms of schizophrenia, and goal-directed behaviour, a neuropsychological hypothesis is proposed for the generation of the contents of consciousness. It is suggested that these correspond to the outputs of a comparator that, on a moment-by-moment basis, compares the current state of the organism's perceptual world with a predicted state. An outline is given of the information-processing functions of the comparator system and of the neural systems which mediate them. The hypothesis (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Rule systems are not dead: Existential quantifiers are harder.Richard E. Grandy - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):351-352.
  • Consciousness and its (dis)contents.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):703-722.
    The first claim in the target article was that there is as yet no transparent, causal account of the relations between consciousness and brain-and-behaviour. That claim remains firm. The second claim was that the contents of consciousness consist, psychologically, of the outputs of a comparator system; the third consisted of a description of the brain mechanisms proposed to instantiate the comparator. In order to defend these claims against criticism, it has been necessary to clarify the distinction between consciousness-as-such and the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Uncertainty about information.Ian E. Gordon - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):146-146.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teleology and agency in speech production.Robert M. Gordon - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):525-525.
  • Self-ascription of belief and desire.Robert M. Gordon - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):45-46.
  • Some distinctions among representations.M. Gopnik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):378-379.
  • Theories and illusions.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):90-100.
  • Theories and qualities.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):44-45.
  • How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):1-14.
  • The relation between epistemology and psychology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1985 - Synthese 64 (1):29-68.
    In the wake of Frege's attack on psychologism and the subsequent influence of Logical Positivism, psychological considerations in philosophy came to be viewed with suspicion. Philosophical questions, especially epistemological ones, were viewed as 'logical' questions, and logic was sharply separated from psychology. Various efforts have been made of late to reconnect epistemology with psychology. But there is little agreement about how such connections should be made, and doubts about the place of psychology within epistemology are still much in evidence. It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The psychology of folk psychology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):15-28.
    The central mission of cognitive science is to reveal the real nature of the mind, however familiar or foreign that nature may be to naive preconceptions. The existence of naive conceptions is also important, however. Prescientific thought and language contain concepts of the mental, and these concepts deserve attention from cognitive science. Just as scientific psychology studies folk physics (McCloskey 1983, Hayes 1985), viz., the common understanding (or misunderstanding) of physical phenomena, so it must study folk psychology, the common understanding (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   220 citations  
  • On some specific models of intentional behavior.Richard M. Golden - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):144-145.
  • Functionalism, the theory-theory and phenomenology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):101-108.
    The ordinary understanding and ascription of mental states is a multiply complex subject. Widely discussed approaches to the subject, such as functionalism and the theory-theory (TT), have many variations and interpretations. No surprise, then, that there are misunderstandings and disagreements, which place many items on the agenda. Unfortunately, the multiplicity of issues raised by the commentators and the limitations of space make it impossible to give a full reply to everyone. My response is divided into five topics: (1) Which version(s) (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Competing accounts of belief-task performance.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):43-44.
  • Ambiguities in “the algorithmic level”.Alvin I. Goldman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):484-485.
  • ERP evidence for task modulations on face perceptual processing at different spatial scales.Valérie Goffaux, Boutheina Jemel, Corentin Jacques, Bruno Rossion & Philippe G. Schyns - 2003 - Cognitive Science 27 (2):313-325.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why Semantic Properties Won’t Earn their Keep.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 50 (September):223-36.
  • The strategy used to increase the amplitude of the movement varies with the muscle studied.Emile Godaux - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):219-219.
  • Determining the primary problem of visual perception: A Gibsonian response to the correlation' objection.Philip A. Glotzbach - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (1):69-94.
    Fodor & Pylyshyn (1981) criticize J. J. Gibson's ecological account of perception for failing to address what I call the 'correlation problem' in visual perception. That is, they charge that Gibson cannot explain how perceivers learn to correlate detectable properties of the light with perceptible properties of the environment. Furthermore, they identify the correlation problem as a crucial issue for any theory of visual perception, what I call a 'primary problem'—i.e. a problem which plays a definitive role in establishing the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The study of cognition and instructional design: Mutual nurturance.Robert Glaser - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):483-484.
  • Arousal and the disruption of language production processes in schizophrenia.Per F. Gjerde - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):524-524.
  • If a particular strategy is used, what aspects of the movement are controlled?C. C. A. M. Gielen & J. J. Denier van der Gon - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):218-219.
  • Species are individuals: Therefore human nature is a metaphysical delusion.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):77-78.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Strategies are a means to an end.C. Ghez & J. Gordon - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):216-218.
  • Challenges to the Modularity Thesis Under the Bayesian Brain Models.Nithin George & Meera Mary Sunny - 2019 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 13.