Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Amplifying sociobiology's hollow ring.Timothy D. Johnston - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):78-79.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is circulation a conditional operant or has a behaviorist discovered cognitive structures?J. Richard Jennings - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):298-299.
  • Representations as metaphiers.Julian Jaynes - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):379-380.
  • Hearing voices and the bicameral mind.Julian Jaynes - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):526-527.
  • Qualia for propositional attitudes?Frank Jackson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):52-52.
  • Colby's paranoia model: An old theory in a new frame?C. E. Izard & F. A. Masterson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):539-540.
  • Information synthesis in cortical areas as an important link in brain mechanisms of mind.Alexei M. Ivanitsky - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):686-687.
    To explore the mechanism of sensation correlations between EP component amplitude and signal detection indices were studied. The time of sensation coincided with the peak latency of those EP components that showed a correlation with both indices. The components presumably reflected information synthesis in projection cortical neurons. A mechanism providing the synthesis process is proposed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mind – your head!R. P. Ingvaldsen & H. T. A. Whiting - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):685-686.
    Gray takes an information-processing paradigm as his departure point, invoking a comparator as part of the system. He concludes that consciousness is to be found “in” the comparator but is unable to point to how the comparison takes place. Thus, the comparator turns out not to be an entity arising out of brain research per se, but out of the logic of the paradigm. In this way, Gray both reinvents dualism and remains trapped in the language game of his own (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Architecture and algorithms: Power sharing for mental models.Robert Inder - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):354-354.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Codes, relations, and mappings.J. Wesley Hutchinson - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):149-149.
  • Perspective, reflection, transparent explanation, and other minds.S. L. Hurley - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):684-685.
    Perspective and reflection have each been considered in some way basic to phenomenal consciousness. Each has possible evolutionary value, though neither seems sufficient for consciousness. Consider an account of consciousness in terms of the combination of perspective and reflection, its relationship to the problem of other minds, and its capacity to inherit evolutionary explanation from its components.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The language of componential analysis.Earl Hunt - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):592-595.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental visualization in nonlaboratory situations.Ian M. L. Hunter - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):556-557.
  • A case study of how a paper containing good ideas, presented by a distinguished scientist, to an appropriate audience, had almost no influence at all.Earl Hunt - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):597-598.
  • Tags, alphabets, and the neglect of sound.Stewart H. Hulse - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):148-149.
  • Comparative cognition revisited.Stewart H. Hulse - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):379-379.
  • Hebb's accomplishments misunderstood.Michael Hucka, Mark Weaver & Stephen Kaplan - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):635-636.
    Amit's efforts to provide stronger theoretical and empirical support for Hebb's cell-assembly concept is admirable, but we have serious reservations about the perspective presented in the target article. For Hebb, the cell assembly was a building block; by contrast, the framework proposed here eschews the need to fit the assembly into a broader picture of its function.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bursts of discharge recorded from the red nucleus may provide real measures of Gottlieb's excitation pulses.James C. Houk - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):224-225.
  • Symbols and Computation A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind.Steven Horst - 1999 - Minds and Machines 9 (3):347-381.
    Over the past several decades, the philosophical community has witnessed the emergence of an important new paradigm for understanding the mind.1 The paradigm is that of machine computation, and its influence has been felt not only in philosophy, but also in all of the empirical disciplines devoted to the study of cognition. Of the several strategies for applying the resources provided by computer and cognitive science to the philosophy of mind, the one that has gained the most attention from philosophers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Analytic functionalism without representational functionalism.Terence Horgan - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):51-51.
  • Two ways to reduce motor programming load.Dennis H. Holding - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):224-224.
  • On choosing the “right” stimulus and rule.Robin M. Hogarth - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):596-596.
  • What can schizophrenic “voices” tell us?Ralph E. Hoffman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):535-548.
  • Verbal hallucinations and language production processes in schizophrenia.Ralph E. Hoffman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):503-517.
    How is it that many schizophrenics identify certain instances of verbal imagery as hallucinatory? Most investigators have assumed that alterations in sensory features of imagery explain this. This approach, however, has not yielded a definitive picture of the nature of verbal hallucinations. An alternative perspective suggests itself if one allows the possibility that the nonself quality of hallucinations is inferred on the basis of the experience of unintendedness that accompanies imagery production. Information-processing models of “intentional” cognitive processes call for abstract (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Reductionism and religion.Douglas R. Hofstadter - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):433-434.
  • Force requirements and patterns of muscle activity.Donna S. Hoffman & Peter L. Strick - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):221-224.
  • Additional tests of Amit's attractor neural networks.Ralph E. Hoffman - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):634-635.
    Further tests of Amit's model are indicated. One strategy is to use the apparent coding sparseness of the model to make predictions about coding sparseness in Miyashita's network. A second approach is to use memory overload to induce false positive responses in modules and biological systems. In closing, the importance of temporal coding and timing requirements in developing biologically plausible attractor networks is mentioned.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logical content of theories of deduction.Wilfrid Hodges - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):353-354.
  • Mathematics of Hebbian attractors.Morris W. Hirsch - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):633-634.
    The concept of an attractor in a mathematical dynamical system is reviewed. Emphasis is placed on the distinction between a cell assembly, the corresponding attractor, and the attractor dynamics. The biological significance of these entities is discussed, especially the question of whether the representation of the stimulus requires the full attractor dynamics, or merely the cell assembly as a set of reverberating neurons. Comparison is made to Freeman's study of dynamic patterns in olfaction.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Enactive-Dynamic Social Cognition and Active Inference.Inês Hipólito & Thomas van Es - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    This aim of this paper is two-fold: it critically analyses and rejects accounts blending active inference as theory of mind and enactivism; and it advances an enactivist-dynamic understanding of social cognition that is compatible with active inference. While some social cognition theories seemingly take an enactive perspective on social cognition, they explain it as the attribution of mental states to other people, by assuming representational structures, in line with the classic Theory of Mind. Holding both enactivism and ToM, we argue, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Inferring the meaning of direct perception.Geoffrey E. Hinton - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):387-388.
  • Imagery without arrays.Geoffrey Hinton - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):555-556.
  • Qualitative characteristics, type materialism and the circularity of analytic functionalism.Christopher S. Hill - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):50-51.
  • Movement strategies as points on equal-outcome curves.Herbert Heuer - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):220-221.
  • A flawed analogy?James Hendler - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):485-486.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychopathology and the discontinuity of conscious experience.David R. Hemsley - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):683-684.
    It is accepted that “primary awareness” may emerge from the integration of two classes of information. It is unclear, however, why this cannot take place within the comparator rather than in conjunction with feedback to the perceptual systems. The model has plausibility in relation to the continuity of conscious experience in the normal waking state and may be extended to encompass certain aspects of the “sense of self” which are frequently disrupted in psychotic patients.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental Imagery and mystification.John Hell - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):554-555.
  • Unraveling introspection.John Heil - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):49-50.
  • Intentionality and the explanation of behavior.John Heil - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):146-147.
  • Simulation and cognitive penetrability.Jane Heal - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (1):44-67.
    : Stich, Nichols et al. assert that the process of deriving predictions by simulation must be cognitively impenetrable. Hence, they claim, the occurrence of certain errors in prediction provides empirical evidence against simulation theory. But it is false that simulation‐derived prediction must be cognitively impenetrable. Moreover the errors they cite, which are instances of irrationality, are not evidence against the version of simulation theory that takes the central domain of simulation to be intelligible transitions between states with content.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Simulation and Cognitive Penetrability.Jane Heal - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (1):44-67.
    Stich, Nichols et al. assert that the process of deriving predictions by simulation must be cognitively impenetrable. Hence, they claim, the occurrence of certain errors in prediction provides empirical evidence against simulation theory. But it is false that simulation‐derived prediction must be cognitively impenetrable. Moreover the errors they cite, which are instances of irrationality, are not evidence against the (very defensible) version of simulation theory that takes the central domain of simulation to be intelligible transitions between states with content.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Understanding mental imagery: interpretive metaphors versus explanatory models.Frederick Hayes-Roth - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):553-554.
  • Mediating the so-called immediate processes of perception.Frederick Hayes-Roth - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):386-387.
  • Task variables and the saturation of the excitation pulse.Z. Hasan & G. M. Karst - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):219-220.
  • Representationalism vs. anti-representationalism: A debate for the sake of appearance.Pim Haselager, Andre´ de Groot & Hans van Rappard - 2003 - Philosophical Psychology 16 (1):5-23.
    In recent years the cognitive science community has witnessed the rise of a new, dynamical approach to cognition. This approach entails a framework in which cognition and behavior are taken to result from complex dynamical interactions between brain, body, and environment. The advent of the dynamical approach is grounded in a dissatisfaction with the classical computational view of cognition. A particularly strong claim has been that cognitive systems do not rely on internal representations and computations. Focusing on this claim, we (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Verbal hallucinations and speech disorganization in schizophrenia: A further look at the evidence.Martin Harrow, Joanne T. Marengo & Ann Ragin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):526-526.
  • The Semantic Content of Abstract Concepts: A Property Listing Study of 296 Abstract Words.Marcel Harpaintner, Natalie M. Trumpp & Markus Kiefer - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
  • Speech errors and hallucinations in schizophrenia – no difference?Trevor A. Harley - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):525-526.
  • Reduction, explanatory extension, and the mind/brain sciences.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1992 - Philosophy of Science 59 (3):408-28.
    In trying to characterize the relationship between psychology and neuroscience, the trend has been to argue that reductionism does not work without suggesting a suitable substitute. I offer explanatory extension as a good model for elucidating the complex relationship among disciplines which are obviously connected but which do not share pragmatic explanatory features. Explanatory extension rests on the idea that one field can "illuminate" issues that were incompletely treated in another. In this paper, I explain how this "illumination" would work (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Psychology as moral rhetoric.Rom Harré - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):595-596.