Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Intentionality, mind and folk psychology.Winand H. Dittrich & Stephen E. G. Lea - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):39-41.
    The comment addresses central issues of a "theory theory" approach as exemplified in Gopnik' and Goldman's BBS-articles. Gopnik, on the one hand, tries to demonstrate that empirical evidence from developmental psychology supports the view of a "theory theory" in which common sense beliefs are constructed to explain ourselves and others. Focusing the informational processing routes possibly involved we would like to argue that his main thesis (e.g. idea of intentionality as a cognitive construct) lacks support at least for two reasons: (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computers Are Syntax All the Way Down: Reply to Bozşahin.William J. Rapaport - 2019 - Minds and Machines 29 (2):227-237.
    A response to a recent critique by Cem Bozşahin of the theory of syntactic semantics as it applies to Helen Keller, and some applications of the theory to the philosophy of computer science.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cognitive penetration and the perception of colour.Dustin Stokes - 2021 - In Derek H. Brown & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Colour. New York: Routledge.
    This chapter concerns the cognitive penetration of the visual experience of colour. Alleged cases of cognitively penetrated colour perception are of special import since they concern an uncontroversial type of visual experience. All theorists of perception agree that colour properties figure properly in the content or presentation of visual perception, even though not all parties agree that pine trees or causes or other "high-level" properties can figure properly in visual content or presentation. So an alleged case of this kind does (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1692 citations  
  • The meaning of representation in animal memory.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):353-372.
    A representation is a remnant of previous experience that allows that experience to affect later behavior. This paper develops a metatheoretical view of representation and applies it to issues concerning representation in animals. To describe a representational system one must specify the following: thedomainor range of situations in the represented world to which the system applies; thecontentor set of features encoded and preserved by the system; thecodeor transformational rules relating features of the representation to the corresponding features of the represented (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • An essay on the circulation as behavior.Bernard T. Engel - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):285-295.
    Most conceptual models of the organization of the cardiovascular system begin with the premise that the nervous system regulates the metabolic and nonmetabolic reflex adjustments of the circulation. These models assume that all the neurally mediated responses of the circulation are reactive, i.e., reflexes elicited by adequate stimuli. This target article suggests that the responses of the circulation are conditional in three senses. First, as Sherrington argued, reflexes are conditional in that they never operate in a vacuum but in a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • On simple movements and complex theories (and vice versa).K. M. Newell, R. E. A. Van Emmerik & P. V. McDonald - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):229-230.
  • On simple movements and complex theories (and vice versa).K. M. Newell, R. E. A. van Emmerik & P. V. McDonald - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):229-230.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Strategies for the control of voluntary movements with one mechanical degree of freedom.Gerald L. Gottlieb, Daniel M. Corcos & Gyan C. Agarwal - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):189-210.
    A theory is presented to explain how accurate, single-joint movements are controlled. The theory applies to movements across different distances, with different inertial loads, toward targets of different widths over a wide range of experimentally manipulated velocities. The theory is based on three propositions. (1) Movements are planned according to “strategies” of which there are at least two: a speed-insensitive (SI) and a speed-sensitive (SS) one. (2) These strategies can be equated with sets of rules for performing diverse movement tasks. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • Mechanisms in Cognitive Science.Carlos Zednik - 2017 - In Stuart Glennan & Phyllis McKay Illari (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and Mechanical Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 389-400.
    This chapter subsumes David Marr’s levels of analysis account of explanation in cognitive science under the framework of mechanistic explanation: Answering the questions that define each one of Marr’s three levels is tantamount to describing the component parts and operations of mechanisms, as well as their organization, behavior, and environmental context. By explicating these questions and showing how they are answered in several different cognitive science research programs, this chapter resolves some of the ambiguities that remain in Marr’s account, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Environments of Intelligence. From Natural Information to Artficial Interaction.Hajo Greif - 2017 - London: Routledge.
    What is the role of the environment, and of the information it provides, in cognition? More specifically, may there be a role for certain artefacts to play in this context? These are questions that motivate "4E" theories of cognition (as being embodied, embedded, extended, enactive). In his take on that family of views, Hajo Greif first defends and refines a concept of information as primarily natural, environmentally embedded in character, which had been eclipsed by information-processing views of cognition. He continues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive maps and the language of thought.Michael Rescorla - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (2):377-407.
    Fodor advocates a view of cognitive processes as computations defined over the language of thought (or Mentalese). Even among those who endorse Mentalese, considerable controversy surrounds its representational format. What semantically relevant structure should scientific psychology attribute to Mentalese symbols? Researchers commonly emphasize logical structure, akin to that displayed by predicate calculus sentences. To counteract this tendency, I discuss computational models of navigation drawn from probabilistic robotics. These models involve computations defined over cognitive maps, which have geometric rather than logical (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • What are the contributions of the direct perception approach?Carl B. Zuckerman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):407-408.
  • The computational/representational paradigm as normal science: further support.Steven W. Zucker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):406-407.
  • Image or neural coding of inner speech and agency?Gail Zivin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):534-535.
  • The heuristic value of representation.Thomas R. Zentall - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-394.
  • Abstract codes are not just for chimpanzees.Thomas R. Zentall - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):157-158.
  • The psychologist's fallacy.Philip David Zelazo & Douglas Frye - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):89-90.
  • Intentionality, theoreticity and innateness.Deborah Zaitchik & Jerry Samet - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):87-89.
  • Advances and retreats In laterality research.Eran Zaidel - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):523.
  • Control of autonomic nervous system-mediated behaviors: exploring the limits.Absalom M. Yellin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):305-306.
  • Program control of circulatory behavior.Robert D. Wurster - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):305-305.
  • To what extent do beliefs affect apparent motion?Richard D. Wright & Michael R. W. Dawson - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (4):471-491.
    A number of studies in the apparent motion literature were examined using the cognitive penetrability criterion to determine the extent to which beliefs affect the perception of apparent motion. It was found that the interaction between the perceptual processes mediating apparent motion and higher order processes appears to be limited. In addition, perceptual and inferential beliefs appear to have different effects on perceived motion optimality and direction. Our findings suggest that the system underlying apparent motion perception has more than one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How do local reverberations achieve global integration?J. J. Wright - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):644-645.
    Amit's Hebbian model risks being overexplanatory, since it does not depend on specific physiological modelling of cortical ANNs, but concentrates on those phenomena which are modelled by a large class of ANNs. While offering a strong demonstration of the presence of Hebb's “cell assemblies,” it does not offer an equal account of Hebb's “phase sequence” concept.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three questions for Goldman.Andrew Woodfield - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):86-87.
  • Circulatory behavior: Historical perspective and projections for the future.Stewart Wolf - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):304-305.
  • What is adapted in strategy-governed movements?U. Windhorst - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):236-237.
  • Searle's straw men.Yorick Wilks - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):344-345.
  • Mind the brain.Martha Wilson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-393.
  • Computers, cognition and philosophy.Robert Wilensky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):449-450.
  • More models just means more difficulty.N. E. Wetherick - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):367-368.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Negation in Skinner's system.N. E. Wetherick - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):606-607.
  • Percepts, intervening variables, and neural mechanisms.Wally Welker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):405-406.
  • Logical atomism and computation do not refute Gibson.Walter B. Welmer - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):405-405.
  • Why are “strategies’ senstitive? Smoothing the way for raison d'àtre”.John P. Wann, Ian Nimmo-Smith & Alan M. Wing - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):235-236.
  • The thermostat and the philosophy professor.Donald O. Walter - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):449-449.
  • The pros and cons of having a word for it.S. F. Walker - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):156-157.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the function of mental imagery.David L. Waltz - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):569-570.
  • Massively Parallel Parsing: A Strongly Interactive Model of Natural Language Interpretation.David L. Waltz & Jordan B. Pollack - 1985 - Cognitive Science 9 (1):51-74.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Initiating voluntary movements: Wrong theories for the wrong behaviour?Stephen A. Wallace & Douglas L. Weeks - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):233-234.
  • Elementary conditions for elemental movement strategies.Charles B. Walter - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):234-235.
  • In defense of invariances and higher-order stimuli.K. von Fieandt - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):404-405.
  • The egg revealed.William S. Verplanck - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):605-606.
  • The limits of neuropsychological models of consciousness.Max Velmans - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):702-703.
    This commentary elaborates on Gray's conclusion that his neurophysiological model of consciousness might explain how consciousness arises from the brain, but does not address how consciousness evolved, affects behaviour or confers survival value. The commentary argues that such limitations apply to all neurophysiological or other third-person perspective models. To approach such questions the first-person nature of consciousness needs to be taken seriously in combination with third-person models of the brain.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Common sense, functional theories and knowledge of the mind.Max Velmans - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):85-86.
    A commentary on a target article by Alison Gopnik (1993) How we know our minds: the illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality. Focusing on evidence of how children acquire a theory of mind, this commentary argues that there are internal inconsistencies in theories that both argue for the functional role of conscious experiences and the irreducibility of those experiences to third-person viewable information processing.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Internal representations and indeterminacy: A skeptical view.William R. Uttal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):392-393.
  • Consciousness does not seem to be linked to a single neural mechanism.Carlo Umiltà & Marco Zorzi - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):701-702.
    On the basis of neuropsychological evidence, it is clear that attention should be given a role in any model of consciousness. What is known about the many instances of dissociation between explicit and implicit knowledge after brain damage suggests that conscious experience might not be linked to a restricted area of the brain. Even if it were true that there is a single brain area devoted to consciousness, the subicular area would seem to be an unlikely possibility.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Perception, information, and computation.S. Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):408-415.
  • Against direct perception.Shimon Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):333-81.
    Central to contemporary cognitive science is the notion that mental processes involve computations defined over internal representations. This view stands in sharp contrast to the to visual perception and cognition, whose most prominent proponent has been J.J. Gibson. In the direct theory, perception does not involve computations of any sort; it is the result of the direct pickup of available information. The publication of Gibson's recent book (Gibson 1979) offers an opportunity to examine his approach, and, more generally, to contrast (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Scientific thinking and mental models.Ryan D. Tweney - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):366-367.