Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. In defense of exaptation.Wendy Wilkins & Jennie Dumford - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):763-764.
  • Autonomy and the nature of the input.Wendy Wilkins - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):638-638.
  • Advanced sensorimotor intelligence in Cebus and Macaca.Gregory Charles Westergaard & Gene P. Sackett - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):609-610.
  • Parameter setting and early emergence.Amy Weinberg - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):637-638.
  • Debatable constraints.Thomas Wasow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):636-637.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Primate tool use: Parsimonious explanations make better science.Elisabetta Visalberghi - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):608-609.
  • Natural Language and Logic of Agency.Johan van Benthem - 2014 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 23 (3):367-382.
    This light piece reflects on analogies between two often disjoint streams of research: the logical semantics and pragmatics of natural language and dynamic logics of general information-driven agency. The two areas show significant overlap in themes and tools, and yet, the focus seems subtly different in each, defying a simple comparison. We discuss some unusual questions that emerge when the two are put side by side, without any pretense at covering the whole literature or at reaching definitive conclusions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why chimps matter to language origin.Ib Ulbaek - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):762-763.
  • Toward an adaptationist psycholinguistics.John Tooby & Leda Cosmides - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):760-762.
  • Grammar yes, generative grammar no.Michael Tomasello - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):759-760.
  • Cognition as cause.Michael Tomasello - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):607-608.
  • The view of language.Michael Studdert-Kennedy - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):758-759.
  • The evolution of the language faculty: A paradox and its solution.Dan Sperber - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-758.
  • A premature retreat to nativism.Jeffrey L. Sokolov & Catherine E. Snow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):635-636.
  • Anatomizing the rhinoceros.Elliott Sober - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):764-765.
  • Can Crain constrain the constraints?Dan I. Slobin - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):633-634.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Innate universals do not solve the negative feedback problem.I. M. Schlesinger - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):633-633.
  • Tool use in monkeys.Sue Savage-Rumbaugh, Karen Brakke & Krista Wilkinson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):606-607.
  • Apples and oranges: The pitfalls of comparative intelligence.Anne Savage & Charles T. Snowdon - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):605-606.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Maturation, emergence and performance.Jerry Samet & Helen Tager-Flusberg - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):631-632.
  • Nativism in cognitive science.Richard Samuels - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (3):233-65.
    Though nativist hypotheses have played a pivotal role in the development of cognitive science, it remains exceedingly obscure how they—and the debates in which they figure—ought to be understood. The central aim of this paper is to provide an account which addresses this concern and in so doing: a) makes sense of the roles that nativist theorizing plays in cognitive science and, moreover, b), explains why it really matters to the contemporary study of cognition. I conclude by outlining a range (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • We need a team of gene-mappers, not principle-provers.Thomas Roeper - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):630-631.
  • Arbitrariness no argument against adaption.Mark Ridley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-756.
  • Remembering Jerry Fodor and his work.Georges Rey - 2018 - Mind and Language 33 (4):321-341.
    This is a reminiscence and short biographical sketch of the late philosopher and cognitive scientist Jerry Fodor. It includes a summary of his main proposals about the mind: his “Language of Thought” hypothesis; his rejection of analyticity and conceptual role semantics; his “mad dog nativism”; his proposal of mental modules and—by contrast—his skepticism about a computational theory of central cognition; his anti‐reductionist, but still physicalist, views about psychology; and, lastly, his attacks on selectionism. I conclude with some discussion of his (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the coevolution of language and social competence.David Premack - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):754-756.
  • Language acquisition in the absence of proof of absence of experience.David M. W. Powers - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):629-630.
  • Natural language and natural selection.Steven Pinker & Paul Bloom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):707-27.
    Many people have argued that the evolution of the human language faculty cannot be explained by Darwinian natural selection. Chomsky and Gould have suggested that language may have evolved as the by-product of selection for other abilities or as a consequence of as-yet unknown laws of growth and form. Others have argued that a biological specialization for grammar is incompatible with every tenet of Darwinian theory – that it shows no genetic variation, could not exist in any intermediate forms, confers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   598 citations  
  • Issues in the evolution of the human language faculty.Steven Pinker & Paul Bloom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):765-784.
  • Acquisition errors in the absence of experience.A. E. Pierce - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):628-629.
  • An ideological battle over modals and quantifiers.Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):752-754.
  • Complexity and adaptation.David Pesetsky & Ned Block - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):750-752.
  • Tool use in birds: An avian monkey wrench?Irene M. Pepperberg - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):604-605.
  • Universal grammar and mental continuity: Two modern myths.Derek C. Penn, Keith J. Holyoak & Daniel J. Povinelli - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (5).
    In our opinion, the discontinuity between extant human and nonhuman minds is much broader and deeper than most researchers admit. We are happy to report that Evans & Levinson's (E&L's) target article strongly corroborates our unpopular hypothesis, and that the comparative evidence, in turn, bolsters E&L's provocative argument. Both a Universal Grammar and the “mental continuity” between human and nonhuman minds turn out to be modern myths.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Imitation and derivative reactions.Sue Taylor Parker - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):604-604.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The acquisition of modality: Implications for theories of semantic representation.Anna Papafragou - 1998 - Mind and Language 13 (3):370–399.
    The set of English modal verbs is widely recognized to communicate two broad clusters of meanings: epistemic and root modal meanings. A number of researchers have claimed that root meanings are acquired earlier than epistemic ones; this claim has subsequently been employed in the linguistics literature as an argument for the position that English modal verbs are polysemous (Sweetser, 1990). In this paper I offer an alternative explanation for the later emergence of epistemic interpretations by linking them to the development (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The emergence of homo loquens and the laws of physics.Carlos P. Otero - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):747-750.
  • The genome might as well store the entire language in the environment.Anat Ninio - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):746-747.
  • Natural selection and the autonomy of syntax.Frederick J. Newmeyer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):745-746.
  • Laura: A Case for the Modularity of Language.Neil Smith - 1991 - Mind and Language 6 (4):390-396.
  • Returning language to culture by way of biology.Bjorn Merker, Nicholas Evans & Stephen C. Levinson - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (5):460-461.
    Conflation of our unique human endowment for language with innate, so-called universal, grammar has banished language from its biological home. The facts reviewed by Evans & Levinson (E&L) fit the biology of cultural transmission. My commentary highlights our dedicated learning capacity for vocal production learning as the form of our language endowment compatible with those facts.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is intelligent behavior a directly observable phenomenon?E. W. Menzel - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):603-604.
  • “Negative evidence” and the gratuitous leap from principles to parameters.James D. McCawley - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):627-628.
  • Middle position on language, cognition, and evolution.Michael Maratsos - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):744-745.
  • Causal stories.David Magnus - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):744-744.
  • Tool use implies sensorimotor skill: But differences in skills do not imply differences in intelligence.Euan M. Macphail - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):602-603.
  • Logic and language acquisition.F. Lowenthal - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):626-627.
  • Chomsky on the 'ordinary language' view of language.Francis Y. Lin - 1999 - Synthese 120 (2):151-191.
    There is a common-sense view of language, which is held by Wittgenstein, Strawson Dummett, Searle, Putnam, Lewis, Wiggins, and others. According to this view a language consists of conventions, it is rule-governed, rules are conventionalised, a language is learnt, there are general learning mechanisms in the brain, and so on. I shall call this view the ‘ ordinary language ’ view of language. Chomsky’s attitude towards this view of language has been rather negative, and his rejection of it is a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptive complexity in sound patterns.Björn Lindblom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):743-744.
  • Language evolved – So what's new?John Limber - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):742-743.
  • Not invented here.Philip Lieberman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):741-742.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark