Switch to: References

Citations of:

Moral Practices

Philosophy 46 (176):179-181 (1970)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. “Ought” Implies “Can” but Does Not Imply “Must”: An Asymmetry between Becoming Infeasible and Becoming Overridden.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2018 - Philosophical Review 127 (4):487-514.
    The claim that (OIC) “ought” implies “can” (i.e., you have an obligation only at times at which you can obey it) entails that (1) obligations that become infeasible are lost (i.e., you stop having an obligation when you become unable to obey it). Moreover, the claim that (2) obligations that become overridden are not always lost (i.e., sometimes you keep having an obligation when you acquire a stronger incompatible obligation) entails that (ONIM) “ought” does not imply “must” (i.e., some obligations (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The idea of an ethically committed social science.Leonidas Tsilipakos - 2022 - History of the Human Sciences 35 (2):144-166.
    This article presents a long overdue analysis of the idea of an ethically committed social science, which, after the demise of positivism and the deeming of moral neutrality as impossible, has come to dominate the self-understanding of many contemporary sociological approaches. Once adequately specified, however, the idea is shown to be ethically questionable in that it works against the moral commitments constitutive of academic life. The argument is conducted with resources from the work of Peter Winch, thus establishing its continuing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On "Moral Expertise".Béla Szabados - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1):117 - 129.
    Not so long ago it was fashionable to claim that it is not the moral philosopher's business to say what things are good or what actions we should perform. This view is succinctly stated by A. J. Ayer:There is a distinction, which is not always sufficiently marked, between the activity of a moralist, who sets out to elaborate a moral code, or to encourage its observance, and that of a moral philosopher, whose concern is not primarily to make moral judgments (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On.Béla Szabados - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1):117-129.
    Not so long ago it was fashionable to claim that it is not the moral philosopher's business to say what things are good or what actions we should perform. This view is succinctly stated by A. J. Ayer:There is a distinction, which is not always sufficiently marked, between the activity of a moralist, who sets out to elaborate a moral code, or to encourage its observance, and that of a moral philosopher, whose concern is not primarily to make moral judgments (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The pervasiveness of species bias.Peter Singer - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):759-761.
  • Assessing animal welfare: Design versus Performance criteria.Jeffrey Rushen - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):758-758.
  • Against Non-Comparabilism.Robin Attfield - 1975 - Philosophy 50 (192):230 - 234.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Coffee to Carmelites. [REVIEW]D. Z. Phillips - 1990 - Philosophy 65 (251):19-38.
    In his paper, ‘The Aroma of Coffee’, H. O. Mounce wants to expose what he takes to be a deep prejudice in philosophy, one which is at work in our culture more generally. Philosophers are reluctant to admit that there is anything which passes beyond human understanding. Of course, they are quite ready to admit that there are plenty of things that they fail to understand but this they would say simply happens to be the case. It does not mean (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Power of Example.Onora O'Neill - 1986 - Philosophy 61 (235):5 - 29.
    The examples of which he complained were trivial in either or both of two ways. Some were examples of the minor perplexities of life, such as returning library books or annoying the neighbours with one's music; some were examples described only in outline rather than in depth; and some examples were both minor and schematic.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Good, the Bad, and the Impartial.John Horton - 1996 - Utilitas 8 (3):307.
    In Justice as Impartiality Brian Barry seeks to present ‘a universally valid case in favour of liberal egalitarian principles’. It is an ambitious enterprise undertaken with originality, vigour, and wit; and containing a wealth of interesting argumentation. If, ultimately, Barry fails in the task he sets himself, as I shall argue he does, the attempt is none the less highly instructive; not only because of the many local successes in his arguments with proponents of alternative theories and his often illuminating (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Toward positive animal welfare.Clive Hollands - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):757-758.
  • On strangerism and speciesism.J. A. Gray - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):756-757.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Humans' use of animals: On the horns of a moral dilemma.Brian Everill - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):756-756.
  • From Coffee to Carmelites.D. Z. Phillips - 1990 - Philosophy 65 (251):19 - 38.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mill′s Principle of Liberty.Y. N. Chopra - 1994 - Philosophy 69 (270):417-441.
    Although J. S. Mill′s essay On Liberty was intended by its author to be read as a self-contained work,1 and even though a careful reading would justify seeing it in this way, it has far too often been denied this right even by its defenders. There is a crucial distinction to be made between eliciting some point of substance from a particular work by an author and then turning to the rest of his work to throw further light on it, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The animal's point of view, animal welfare and some other related matters.Marc Bekoff - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):753-755.
  • The Nature of Values and Their Place and Promotion in Schemes of Values Education1.D. N. Aspin - 1999 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 31 (2):123-143.