Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Functors and Ordinal Notations. IV: The Howard Ordinal and the Functor $\wedge$??Jacqueline Vauzeilles - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):331-338.
  • What is a Paraconsistent Logic?Damian Szmuc, Federico Pailos & Eduardo Barrio - 2018 - In Walter Carnielli & Jacek Malinowski (eds.), Contradictions, from Consistency to Inconsistency. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    Paraconsistent logics are logical systems that reject the classical principle, usually dubbed Explosion, that a contradiction implies everything. However, the received view about paraconsistency focuses only the inferential version of Explosion, which is concerned with formulae, thereby overlooking other possible accounts. In this paper, we propose to focus, additionally, on a meta-inferential version of Explosion, i.e. which is concerned with inferences or sequents. In doing so, we will offer a new characterization of paraconsistency by means of which a logic is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Proof, Computation and Agency: Logic at the Crossroads.Johan van Benthem, Amitabha Gupta & Rohit Parikh (eds.) - 2011 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Proof, Computation and Agency: Logic at the Crossroads provides an overview of modern logic and its relationship with other disciplines. As a highlight, several articles pursue an inspiring paradigm called 'social software', which studies patterns of social interaction using techniques from logic and computer science. The book also demonstrates how logic can join forces with game theory and social choice theory. A second main line is the logic-language-cognition connection, where the articles collected here bring several fresh perspectives. Finally, the book (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Investigations on slow versus fast growing: How to majorize slow growing functions nontrivially by fast growing ones. [REVIEW]Andreas Weiermann - 1995 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 34 (5):313-330.
    Let T(Ω) be the ordinal notation system from Buchholz-Schütte (1988). [The order type of the countable segmentT(Ω)0 is — by Rathjen (1988) — the proof-theoretic ordinal the proof-theoretic ordinal ofACA 0 + (Π 1 l −TR).] In particular let ↦Ω a denote the enumeration function of the infinite cardinals and leta ↦ ψ0 a denote the partial collapsing operation on T(Ω) which maps ordinals of T(Ω) into the countable segment TΩ 0 of T(Ω). Assume that the (fast growing) extended Grzegorczyk (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Basic logic: Reflection, symmetry, visibility.Giovanni Sambin, Giulia Battilotti & Claudia Faggian - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):979-1013.
    We introduce a sequent calculus B for a new logic, named basic logic. The aim of basic logic is to find a structure in the space of logics. Classical, intuitionistic, quantum and non-modal linear logics, are all obtained as extensions in a uniform way and in a single framework. We isolate three properties, which characterize B positively: reflection, symmetry and visibility. A logical constant obeys to the principle of reflection if it is characterized semantically by an equation binding it with (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Basic logic: reflection, symmetry, visibility.Giovanni Sambin, Giulia Battilotti & Claudia Faggian - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):979-1013.
    We introduce a sequent calculusBfor a new logic, named basic logic. The aim of basic logic is to find a structure in the space of logics. Classical, intuitionistic. quantum and non-modal linear logics, are all obtained as extensions in a uniform way and in a single framework. We isolate three properties, which characterizeBpositively: reflection, symmetry and visibility.A logical constant obeys to the principle of reflection if it is characterized semantically by an equation binding it with a metalinguistic link between assertions, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The role of parameters in bar rule and bar induction.Michael Rathjen - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (2):715-730.
    For several subsystems of second order arithmetic T we show that the proof-theoretic strength of T + (bar rule) can be characterized in terms of T + (bar induction) □ , where the latter scheme arises from the scheme of bar induction by restricting it to well-orderings with no parameters. In addition, we demonstrate that ACA + 0 , ACA 0 + (bar rule) and ACA 0 + (bar induction) □ prove the same Π 1 1 -sentences.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Is Cantor’s Theorem a Dialetheia? Variations on a Paraconsistent Approach to Cantor’s Theorem.Uwe Petersen - forthcoming - Review of Symbolic Logic:1-18.
    The present note was prompted by Weber’s approach to proving Cantor’s theorem, i.e., the claim that the cardinality of the power set of a set is always greater than that of the set itself. While I do not contest that his proof succeeds, my point is that he neglects the possibility that by similar methods it can be shown also that no non-empty set satisfies Cantor’s theorem. In this paper unrestricted abstraction based on a cut free Gentzen type sequential calculus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Propositional quantifiers in labelled natural deduction for normal modal logic.Matteo Pascucci - 2019 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 27 (6):865-894.
    This article concerns the treatment of propositional quantification in a framework of labelled natural deduction for modal logic developed by Basin, Matthews and Viganò. We provide a detailed analysis of a basic calculus that can be used for a proof-theoretic rendering of minimal normal multimodal systems with quantification over stable domains of propositions. Furthermore, we consider variations of the basic calculus obtained via relational theories and domain theories allowing for quantification over possibly unstable domains of propositions. The main result of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A fully classical truth theory characterized by substructural means.Federico Matías Pailos - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):249-268.
    We will present a three-valued consequence relation for metainferences, called CM, defined through ST and TS, two well known substructural consequence relations for inferences. While ST recovers every classically valid inference, it invalidates some classically valid metainferences. While CM works as ST at the inferential level, it also recovers every classically valid metainference. Moreover, CM can be safely expanded with a transparent truth predicate. Nevertheless, CM cannot recapture every classically valid meta-metainference. We will afterwards develop a hierarchy of consequence relations (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Implicit Commitment of Arithmetical Theories and Its Semantic Core.Carlo Nicolai & Mario Piazza - 2019 - Erkenntnis 84 (4):913-937.
    According to the implicit commitment thesis, once accepting a mathematical formal system S, one is implicitly committed to additional resources not immediately available in S. Traditionally, this thesis has been understood as entailing that, in accepting S, we are bound to accept reflection principles for S and therefore claims in the language of S that are not derivable in S itself. It has recently become clear, however, that such reading of the implicit commitment thesis cannot be compatible with well-established positions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • For Oiva Ketonen's 85th birthday.Sara Negri & Jan von Plato - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (4):418-435.
    A way is found to add axioms to sequent calculi that maintains the eliminability of cut, through the representation of axioms as rules of inference of a suitable form. By this method, the structural analysis of proofs is extended from pure logic to free-variable theories, covering all classical theories, and a wide class of constructive theories. All results are proved for systems in which also the rules of weakening and contraction can be eliminated. Applications include a system of predicate logic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Cut Elimination in the Presence of Axioms.Sara Negri & Jan Von Plato - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (4):418-435.
    A way is found to add axioms to sequent calculi that maintains the eliminability of cut, through the representation of axioms as rules of inference of a suitable form. By this method, the structural analysis of proofs is extended from pure logic to free-variable theories, covering all classical theories, and a wide class of constructive theories. All results are proved for systems in which also the rules of weakening and contraction can be eliminated. Applications include a system of predicate logic (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Open questions in reverse mathematics.Antonio Montalbán - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (3):431-454.
    We present a list of open questions in reverse mathematics, including some relevant background information for each question. We also mention some of the areas of reverse mathematics that are starting to be developed and where interesting open question may be found.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The veblen functions for computability theorists.Alberto Marcone & Antonio Montalbán - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):575 - 602.
    We study the computability-theoretic complexity and proof-theoretic strength of the following statements: (1) "If X is a well-ordering, then so is ε X ", and (2) "If X is a well-ordering, then so is φ(α, X)", where α is a fixed computable ordinal and φ represents the two-placed Veblen function. For the former statement, we show that ω iterations of the Turing jump are necessary in the proof and that the statement is equivalent to ${\mathrm{A}\mathrm{C}\mathrm{A}}_{0}^{+}$ over RCA₀. To prove the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The maximal linear extension theorem in second order arithmetic.Alberto Marcone & Richard A. Shore - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (5-6):543-564.
    We show that the maximal linear extension theorem for well partial orders is equivalent over RCA0 to ATR0. Analogously, the maximal chain theorem for well partial orders is equivalent to ATR0 over RCA0.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • From axioms to synthetic inference rules via focusing.Sonia Marin, Dale Miller, Elaine Pimentel & Marco Volpe - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (5):103091.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some theories with positive induction of ordinal strength ϕω.Gerhard Jäger & Thomas Strahm - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (3):818-842.
    This paper deals with: (i) the theory ID # 1 which results from $\widehat{\mathrm{ID}}_1$ by restricting induction on the natural numbers to formulas which are positive in the fixed point constants, (ii) the theory BON(μ) plus various forms of positive induction, and (iii) a subtheory of Peano arithmetic with ordinals in which induction on the natural numbers is restricted to formulas which are Σ in the ordinals. We show that these systems have proof-theoretic strength φω 0.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On Feferman’s operational set theory OST.Gerhard Jäger - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 150 (1-3):19-39.
    We study and some of its most important extensions primarily from a proof-theoretic perspective, determine their consistency strengths by exhibiting equivalent systems in the realm of traditional set theory and introduce a new and interesting extension of which is conservative over.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • About the proof-theoretic ordinals of weak fixed point theories.Gerhard Jäger & Barbara Primo - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):1108-1119.
    This paper presents several proof-theoretic results concerning weak fixed point theories over second order number theory with arithmetic comprehension and full or restricted induction on the natural numbers. It is also shown that there are natural second order theories which are proof-theoretically equivalent but have different proof-theoretic ordinals.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • One-step Modal Logics, Intuitionistic and Classical, Part 1.Harold T. Hodes - 2021 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 50 (5):837-872.
    This paper and its sequel “look under the hood” of the usual sorts of proof-theoretic systems for certain well-known intuitionistic and classical propositional modal logics. Section 1 is preliminary. Of most importance: a marked formula will be the result of prefixing a formula in a propositional modal language with a step-marker, for this paper either 0 or 1. Think of 1 as indicating the taking of “one step away from 0.” Deductions will be constructed using marked formulas. Section 2 presents (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ordinal inequalities, transfinite induction, and reverse mathematics.Jeffry L. Hirst - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):769-774.
    If α and β are ordinals, α ≤ β, and $\beta \nleq \alpha$ , then α + 1 ≤ β. The first result of this paper shows that the restriction of this statement to countable well orderings is provably equivalent to ACA 0 , a subsystem of second order arithmetic introduced by Friedman. The proof of the equivalence is reminiscent of Dekker's construction of a hypersimple set. An application of the theorem yields the equivalence of the set comprehension scheme ACA (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the Metainferential Solution to the Semantic Paradoxes.Rea Golan - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (3):797-820.
    Substructural solutions to the semantic paradoxes have been broadly discussed in recent years. In particular, according to the non-transitive solution, we have to give up the metarule of Cut, whose role is to guarantee that the consequence relation is transitive. This concession—giving up a meta rule—allows us to maintain the entire consequence relation of classical logic. The non-transitive solution has been generalized in recent works into a hierarchy of logics where classicality is maintained at more and more metainferential levels. All (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Embeddability of ptykes.Jean-Yves Girard & Dag Normann - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (2):659-676.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Proof-theoretic modal pa-completeness I: A system-sequent metric.Paolo Gentilini - 1999 - Studia Logica 63 (1):27-48.
    This paper is the first of a series of three articles that present the syntactic proof of the PA-completeness of the modal system G, by introducing suitable proof-theoretic objects, which also have an independent interest. We start from the syntactic PA-completeness of modal system GL-LIN, previously obtained in [7], [8], and so we assume to be working on modal sequents S which are GL-LIN-theorems. If S is not a G-theorem we define here a notion of syntactic metric d(S, G): we (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Provability logic in the Gentzen formulation of arithmetic.Paolo Gentilini & P. Gentilini - 1992 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 38 (1):535-550.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Two (or three) notions of finitism.Mihai Ganea - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):119-144.
    Finitism is given an interpretation based on two ideas about strings (sequences of symbols): a replacement principle extracted from Hilberts class 2 can be justified by means of an additional finitistic choice principle, thus obtaining a second equational theory . It is unknown whether is strictly stronger than since 2 may coincide with the class of lower elementary functions.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Valuations: Bi, Tri, and Tetra.Rohan French & David Ripley - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (6):1313-1346.
    This paper considers some issues to do with valuational presentations of consequence relations, and the Galois connections between spaces of valuations and spaces of consequence relations. Some of what we present is known, and some even well-known; but much is new. The aim is a systematic overview of a range of results applicable to nonreflexive and nontransitive logics, as well as more familiar logics. We conclude by considering some connectives suggested by this approach.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Valuations: Bi, Tri, and Tetra.Rohan French & David Ripley - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (6):1313-1346.
    This paper considers some issues to do with valuational presentations of consequence relations, and the Galois connections between spaces of valuations and spaces of consequence relations. Some of what we present is known, and some even well-known; but much is new. The aim is a systematic overview of a range of results applicable to nonreflexive and nontransitive logics, as well as more familiar logics. We conclude by considering some connectives suggested by this approach.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Cut as Consequence.Curtis Franks - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (4):349-379.
    The papers where Gerhard Gentzen introduced natural deduction and sequent calculi suggest that his conception of logic differs substantially from the now dominant views introduced by Hilbert, Gödel, Tarski, and others. Specifically, (1) the definitive features of natural deduction calculi allowed Gentzen to assert that his classical system nk is complete based purely on the sort of evidence that Hilbert called ?experimental?, and (2) the structure of the sequent calculi li and lk allowed Gentzen to conceptualize completeness as a question (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The omega-rule interpretation of transfinite provability logic.David Fernández-Duque & Joost J. Joosten - 2018 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 169 (4):333-371.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Arithmetical Reflection and the Provability of Soundness.Walter Dean - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 23 (1):31-64.
    Proof-theoretic reflection principles are schemas which attempt to express the soundness of arithmetical theories within their own language, e.g., ${\mathtt{{Prov}_{\mathsf {PA}} \rightarrow \varphi }}$ can be understood to assert that any statement provable in Peano arithmetic is true. It has been repeatedly suggested that justification for such principles follows directly from acceptance of an arithmetical theory $\mathsf {T}$ or indirectly in virtue of their derivability in certain truth-theoretic extensions thereof. This paper challenges this consensus by exploring relationships between reflection principles (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • On Three-Valued Presentations of Classical Logic.Bruno da Ré, Damian Szmuc, Emmanuel Chemla & Paul Égré - forthcoming - Review of Symbolic Logic:1-23.
    Given a three-valued definition of validity, which choice of three-valued truth tables for the connectives can ensure that the resulting logic coincides exactly with classical logic? We give an answer to this question for the five monotonic consequence relations $st$, $ss$, $tt$, $ss\cap tt$, and $ts$, when the connectives are negation, conjunction, and disjunction. For $ts$ and $ss\cap tt$ the answer is trivial (no scheme works), and for $ss$ and $tt$ it is straightforward (they are the collapsible schemes, in which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Minimal invariant spaces in formal topology.Thierry Coquand - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (3):689-698.
  • (I can’t get no) antisatisfaction.Pablo Cobreros, Elio La Rosa & Luca Tranchini - 2020 - Synthese 198 (9):8251-8265.
    Substructural approaches to paradoxes have attracted much attention from the philosophical community in the last decade. In this paper we focus on two substructural logics, named ST and TS, along with two structural cousins, LP and K3. It is well known that LP and K3 are duals in the sense that an inference is valid in one logic just in case the contrapositive is valid in the other logic. As a consequence of this duality, theories based on either logic are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Sharpened lower bounds for cut elimination.Samuel R. Buss - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):656-668.
    We present sharpened lower bounds on the size of cut free proofs for first-order logic. Prior lower bounds for eliminating cuts from a proof established superexponential lower bounds as a stack of exponentials, with the height of the stack proportional to the maximum depth d of the formulas in the original proof. Our results remove the constant of proportionality, giving an exponential stack of height equal to d — 0(1). The proof method is based on more efficiently expressing the Gentzen-Solovay (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Equalization of finite flowers.Stefano Berardi - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):105-123.
  • Substructural logics, pluralism and collapse.Eduardo Alejandro Barrio, Federico Pailos & Damian Szmuc - 2018 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 20):4991-5007.
    When discussing Logical Pluralism several critics argue that such an open-minded position is untenable. The key to this conclusion is that, given a number of widely accepted assumptions, the pluralist view collapses into Logical Monism. In this paper we show that the arguments usually employed to arrive at this conclusion do not work. The main reason for this is the existence of certain substructural logics which have the same set of valid inferences as Classical Logic—although they are, in a clear (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (Meta)inferential levels of entailment beyond the Tarskian paradigm.Eduardo Alejandro Barrio, Federico Pailos & Damian Szmuc - 2019 - Synthese 198 (S22):5265-5289.
    In this paper we discuss the extent to which the very existence of substructural logics puts the Tarskian conception of logical systems in jeopardy. In order to do this, we highlight the importance of the presence of different levels of entailment in a given logic, looking not only at inferences between collections of formulae but also at inferences between collections of inferences—and more. We discuss appropriate refinements or modifications of the usual Tarskian identity criterion for logical systems, and propose an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Editorial Introduction: Substructural Logics and Metainferences.Eduardo Barrio & Paul Égré - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 51 (6):1215-1231.
    The concept of _substructural logic_ was originally introduced in relation to limitations of Gentzen’s structural rules of Contraction, Weakening and Exchange. Recent years have witnessed the development of substructural logics also challenging the Tarskian properties of Reflexivity and Transitivity of logical consequence. In this introduction we explain this recent development and two aspects in which it leads to a reassessment of the bounds of classical logic. On the one hand, standard ways of defining the notion of logical consequence in classical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anti-exceptionalism, truth and the BA-plan.Eduardo Alejandro Barrio, Federico Pailos & Joaquín Toranzo Calderón - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):12561-12586.
    Anti-exceptionalism about logic states that logical theories have no special epistemological status. Such theories are continuous with scientific theories. Contemporary anti-exceptionalists include the semantic paradoxes as a part of the elements to accept a logical theory. Exploring the Buenos Aires Plan, the recent development of the metainferential hierarchy of ST\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathbf {ST}}$$\end{document}-logics shows that there are multiple options to deal with such paradoxes. There is a whole ST\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the non-confluence of cut-elimination.Matthias Baaz & Stefan Hetzl - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (1):313 - 340.
    We study cut-elimination in first-order classical logic. We construct a sequence of polynomial-length proofs having a non-elementary number of different cut-free normal forms. These normal forms are different in a strong sense: they not only represent different Herbrand-disjunctions but also differ in their propositional structure. This result illustrates that the constructive content of a proof in classical logic is not uniquely determined but rather depends on the chosen method for extracting it.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The metamathematics of ergodic theory.Jeremy Avigad - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 (2-3):64-76.
    The metamathematical tradition, tracing back to Hilbert, employs syntactic modeling to study the methods of contemporary mathematics. A central goal has been, in particular, to explore the extent to which infinitary methods can be understood in computational or otherwise explicit terms. Ergodic theory provides rich opportunities for such analysis. Although the field has its origins in seventeenth century dynamics and nineteenth century statistical mechanics, it employs infinitary, nonconstructive, and structural methods that are characteristically modern. At the same time, computational concerns (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On Formally Measuring and Eliminating Extraneous Notions in Proofs.Andrew Arana - 2009 - Philosophia Mathematica 17 (2):189-207.
    Many mathematicians and philosophers of mathematics believe some proofs contain elements extraneous to what is being proved. In this paper I discuss extraneousness generally, and then consider a specific proposal for measuring extraneousness syntactically. This specific proposal uses Gentzen's cut-elimination theorem. I argue that the proposal fails, and that we should be skeptical about the usefulness of syntactic extraneousness measures.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Identity of Proofs and the Criterion for Admissible Reductions.Seungrak Choi - 2021 - Korean Journal of Logic 3 (24):245-280.
    Dag Prawitz (1971) put forward the idea that an admissible reduction process does not affect the identity of proofs represented by derivations in natural deduction. The idea relies on his conjecture that two derivations represent the same proof if and only if they are equivalent in the sense that they are reflexive, transitive and symmetric closure of the immediate reducibility relation. Schroeder-Heister and Tranchini (2017) accept Prawitz’s conjecture and propose the triviality test as the criterion for admissible reductions. In the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark