Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The structure of amorphous sets.J. K. Truss - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 73 (2):191-233.
    A set is said to be amorphous if it is infinite, but is not the disjoint union of two infinite subsets. Thus amorphous sets can exist only if the axiom of choice is false. We give a general study of the structure which an amorphous set can carry, with the object of eventually obtaining a complete classification. The principal types of amorphous set we distinguish are the following: amorphous sets not of projective type, either bounded or unbounded size of members (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Finite axioms of choice.John Truss - 1973 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 6 (2):147.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • An independence result concerning the axiom of choice.Gershon Sageev - 1975 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 8 (1-2):1-184.
  • Adding dependent choice.David Pincus - 1977 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 11 (1):105.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Levy and set theory.Akihiro Kanamori - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 140 (1):233-252.
    Azriel Levy did fundamental work in set theory when it was transmuting into a modern, sophisticated field of mathematics, a formative period of over a decade straddling Cohen’s 1963 founding of forcing. The terms “Levy collapse”, “Levy hierarchy”, and “Levy absoluteness” will live on in set theory, and his technique of relative constructibility and connections established between forcing and definability will continue to be basic to the subject. What follows is a detailed account and analysis of Levy’s work and contributions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Foundations of nominal techniques: logic and semantics of variables in abstract syntax.Murdoch J. Gabbay - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):161-229.
    We are used to the idea that computers operate on numbers, yet another kind of data is equally important: the syntax of formal languages, with variables, binding, and alpha-equivalence. The original application of nominal techniques, and the one with greatest prominence in this paper, is to reasoning on formal syntax with variables and binding. Variables can be modelled in many ways: for instance as numbers (since we usually take countably many of them); as links (since they may `point' to a (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Model theoretic methods in the theory of isols.Erik Ellentuck - 1978 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 14 (3):273-285.
  • On the Warsaw interactions of logic and mathematics in the years 1919–1939.Roman Duda - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 127 (1-3):289-301.
    The article recalls shortly the early story of cooperation between the already existing Lvov philosophical school, headed by Twardowski, and the just then establishing Warsaw mathematical school, headed by Sierpiski. After that recollection the article proceeds to contributions made by men influenced by the two schools. Most prominent of them was Alfred Tarski whose work in those times, concentrated mainly upon the theory of deduction, axiom of choice, cardinal arithmetic, and measure problem, has been described in some detail.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On o-amorphous sets.P. Creed & J. K. Truss - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 101 (2-3):185-226.
    We study a notion of ‘o-amorphous’ which bears the same relationship to ‘o-minimal’ as ‘amorphous’ 191–233) does to ‘strongly minimal’. A linearly ordered set is said to be o-amorphous if its only subsets are finite unions of intervals. This turns out to be a relatively straightforward case, and we can provide a complete ‘classification’, subject to the same provisos as in Truss . The reason is that since o-amorphous is an essentially second-order notion, it corresponds more accurately to 0-categorical o-minimal, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations