Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Nonindexical Context-Dependence and the Interpretation as Abduction Approach.Erich Rast - 2011 - Lodz Papers in Pragmatics 7 (2):259-279.
    Nonindexical Context-Dependence and the Interpretation as Abduction Approach Inclusive nonindexical context-dependence occurs when the preferred interpretation of an utterance implies its lexically-derived meaning. It is argued that the corresponding processes of free or lexically mandated enrichment can be modeled as abductive inference. A form of abduction is implemented in Simple Type Theory on the basis of a notion of plausibility, which is in turn regarded a preference relation over possible worlds. Since a preordering of doxastic alternatives taken for itself only (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Abstract and Concrete Individuals and Projection.Jiri Raclavsky - 2017 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 24 (supplementary):74-88.
    Two kinds of individuals are distinguished: abstract and concrete. Whereas abstract individuals belong to our conceptual sphere, concrete individuals (i.e. particulars) individuate the world of matter. A subject investigating the external world projects abstract individuals onto concrete ones. The proposal offers a solution to various metaphysical and epistemological puzzles concerned with individuals, e.g., the Ship of Theseus, the Polish Logician, problems with reidentification, or proper names.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Vaghezza: confini, cumuli e paradossi.Sebastiano Moruzzi - 2012 - Roma: Laterza.
  • Quotation and Conceptions of Language.Paul Saka - 2011 - Dialectica 65 (2):205-220.
    This paper discusses empty quotation (‘’ is an empty string) and lexical quotation (his praise was, quote, fulsome, unquote), it challenges the minimal theory of quotation (‘ “x” ’ quotes ‘x’) and it defends the identity theory of quotation. In the process it illuminates disciplinary differences between the science of language and the philosophy of language. First, most philosophers assume, without argument, that language includes writing, whereas linguists have reason to identify language with speech (plus sign language). Second, philosophers tend (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Classes, why and how.Thomas Schindler - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (2):407-435.
    This paper presents a new approach to the class-theoretic paradoxes. In the first part of the paper, I will distinguish classes from sets, describe the function of class talk, and present several reasons for postulating type-free classes. This involves applications to the problem of unrestricted quantification, reduction of properties, natural language semantics, and the epistemology of mathematics. In the second part of the paper, I will present some axioms for type-free classes. My approach is loosely based on the Gödel–Russell idea (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Enciclopédia de Termos Lógico-Filosóficos.João Miguel Biscaia Branquinho, Desidério Murcho & Nelson Gonçalves Gomes (eds.) - 2006 - São Paulo, SP, Brasil: Martins Fontes.
    Esta enciclopédia abrange, de uma forma introdutória mas desejavelmente rigorosa, uma diversidade de conceitos, temas, problemas, argumentos e teorias localizados numa área relativamente recente de estudos, os quais tem sido habitual qualificar como «estudos lógico-filosóficos». De uma forma apropriadamente genérica, e apesar de o território teórico abrangido ser extenso e de contornos por vezes difusos, podemos dizer que na área se investiga um conjunto de questões fundamentais acerca da natureza da linguagem, da mente, da cognição e do raciocínio humanos, bem (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On Representing Information: A Characterization of the Analog/Digital Distinction.Aldo Frigerio, Alessandro Giordani & Luca Mari - 2013 - Dialectica 67 (4):455-483.
    The common account of the analog vs digital distinction is based on features of physical systems, being related to the usage of continuous vs discrete supports respectively. It is proposed here to alternatively characterize the concepts of analog and digital as related to coding systems, of which a formal definition is given, by suggesting that the distinction refers to the strategy adopted to define the coding function: extensional in digital systems, isomorphic intensional in analog systems. This thesis is supported by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Four semantic layers of common nouns.Beihai Zhou & Yi Mao - 2010 - Synthese 175 (1):47 - 68.
    This article proposes a four-layer semantic structure for common nouns. Each layer matches up with a semantic entity of a certain type in Montague’s intensional semantics. It is argued that a common noun denotes a sense and a concept, which are functions. For any given context, the sense of a term determines its extensions and the concept denoted by the term specifies its intensions. Intensions are treated as sets of senses. The membership relation between a sense and an intension is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Twenty-five basic theorems in situation and world theory.Edward N. Zalta - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (4):385-428.
    The foregoing set of theorems forms an effective foundation for the theory of situations and worlds. All twenty-five theorems seem to be basic, reasonable principles that structure the domains of properties, relations, states of affairs, situations, and worlds in true and philosophically interesting ways. They resolve 15 of the 19 choice points defined in Barwise (1989) (see Notes 22, 27, 31, 32, 35, 36, 39, 43, and 45). Moreover, important axioms and principles stipulated by situation theorists are derived (see Notes (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • A comparison of two intensional logics.Edward N. Zalta - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (1):59-89.
    The author examines the differences between the general intensional logic defined in his recent book and Montague's intensional logic. Whereas Montague assigned extensions and intensions to expressions (and employed set theory to construct these values as certain sets), the author assigns denotations to terms and relies upon an axiomatic theory of intensional entities that covers properties, relations, propositions, worlds, and other abstract objects. It is then shown that the puzzles for Montague's analyses of modality and descriptions, propositional attitudes, and directedness (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Theories, theoretical models, truth.Ryszard Wójcicki - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (4):471-516.
  • Theories, theoretical models, truth.Ryszard Wójcicki - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (4):471-516.
  • Theories, theoretical models, truth.Ryszard Wójcicki - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (4):337-406.
    This paper was written with two aims in mind. A large part of it is just an exposition of Tarski's theory of truth. Philosophers do not agree on how Tarski's theory is related to their investigations. Some of them doubt whether that theory has any relevance to philosophical issues and in particular whether it can be applied in dealing with the problems of philosophy (theory) of science.In this paper I argue that Tarski's chief concern was the following question. Suppose a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cartesian vs. Newtonian research strategies for cognitive science.Morton E. Winston - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):463-464.
  • Critical Notice: John Earman's A Primer on Determinism.Mark Wilson - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (3):502-532.
    Your story is there waiting for you, it has been waiting for you there a hundred years, long before you were born and you cannot change a comma of it. Everything you do you have to do. You are the twig, and the water you float on swept you here. You are the leaf, and the breeze you were borne on blew you here. This is your story and you cannot escape it.—Cornell Woolrich, I Married a Dead Man.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Critical notice: John Earman's a Primer on determinism.Mark Wilson - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (3):502-532.
    Your story is there waiting for you, it has been waiting for you there a hundred years, long before you were born and you cannot change a comma of it. Everything you do you have to do. You are the twig, and the water you float on swept you here. You are the leaf, and the breeze you were borne on blew you here. This is your story and you cannot escape it.—Cornell Woolrich, I Married a Dead Man.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Subatomic Natural Deduction for a Naturalistic First-Order Language with Non-Primitive Identity.Bartosz Więckowski - 2016 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 25 (2):215-268.
    A first-order language with a defined identity predicate is proposed whose apparatus for atomic predication is sensitive to grammatical categories of natural language. Subatomic natural deduction systems are defined for this naturalistic first-order language. These systems contain subatomic systems which govern the inferential relations which obtain between naturalistic atomic sentences and between their possibly composite components. As a main result it is shown that normal derivations in the defined systems enjoy the subexpression property which subsumes the subformula property with respect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Cognition and simulation.N. E. Wetherick - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):462-463.
  • On the compositional extension problem.Dag Westerståhl - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (6):549-582.
    A semantics may be compositional and yet partial, in the sense that not all well-formed expressions are assigned meanings by it. Examples come from both natural and formal languages. When can such a semantics be extended to a total one, preserving compositionality? This sort of extension problem was formulated by Hodges, and solved there in a particular case, in which the total extension respects a precise version of the fregean dictum that the meaning of an expression is the contribution it (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • An Indexical Theory of Conditionals.Ken Warmbrōd - 1981 - Dialogue 20 (4):644-664.
    Language theorists have recently come to have an increasing appreciation for the fact that context contributes heavily in determining our interpretation of what is said. Indeed, it now seems clear that no complete understanding of a natural language is possible without some account of the way in which context affects our interpretation of discourse. In this paper, I will attempt to explore one facet of the language – context relationship, namely, the relation between conditionals and context. The first part of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • On putting the cart before the horse: Taking perception seriously in unified theories of cognition.Kim J. Vicente & Alex Kirlik - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):461-462.
  • A cognitive process shell.Steven A. Vere - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):460-461.
  • The Logical Study of Science.Johan van Benthem - 1982 - Synthese 51 (3):431-472.
    The relation between logic and philosophy of science, often taken for granted, is in fact problematic. Although current fashionable criticisms of the usefulness of logic are usually mistaken, there are indeed difficulties which should be taken seriously -- having to do, amongst other things, with different "scientific mentalities" in the two disciplines. Nevertheless, logic is, or should be, a vital part of the theory of science. To make this clear, the bulk of this paper is devoted to the key notion (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Meaning: Interpretation and Inference.Johan van Benthem - 1987 - Synthese 73 (3):451-470.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On models and mechanisms.William R. Uttal - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):459-460.
  • Theory-distance and verisimilitude.Raimo Tuomela - 1978 - Synthese 38 (2):213 - 246.
    Measures of theory-Distance are defined for theories formalizable within first-Order predicate logic by using distributive normal forms. The account is applied to give measures of verisimilitude.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Unified theories and theories that mimic each other's predictions.James T. Townsend - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):458-459.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The application of Montague translations in universal research and typology.Katrin Tent - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (6):661 - 686.
  • Problem spaces, language and connectionism: Issues for cognition.Patrick Suppes - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):457-458.
  • Philosophical implications of Tarski's work.Patrick Suppes - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):80-91.
    In his published work and even more in conversations, Tarski emphasized what he thought were important philosophical aspects of his work. The English translation of his more philosophical papers [56m] was dedicated to his teacher Tadeusz Kotarbinski, and in informal discussions of philosophy he often referred to the influence of Kotarbinski. Also, the influence of Leiniewski, his dissertation adviser, is evident in his early papers. Moreover, some of his important papers of the 1930s were initially given to philosophical audiences. For (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Hand or Hammer? On formal and natural languages in semantics.Martin Stokhof - 2007 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 35 (5-6):597-626.
    This paper does not deal with the topic of ‘the generosity of artificial languages from an Asian or a comparative perspective’. Rather, it is concerned with a particular case taken from a development in the Western tradition, when in the wake of the rise of formal logic at the end of the nineteenth and the beginning of the twentieth century people in philosophy and later in linguistics started to use formal languages in the study of the semantics of natural languages. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Montague’s Theorem and Modal Logic.Johannes Stern - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (3):551-570.
    In the present piece we defend predicate approaches to modality, that is approaches that conceive of modal notions as predicates applicable to names of sentences or propositions, against the challenges raised by Montague’s theorem. Montague’s theorem is often taken to show that the most intuitive modal principles lead to paradox if we conceive of the modal notion as a predicate. Following Schweizer (J Philos Logic 21:1–31, 1992) and others we show this interpretation of Montague’s theorem to be unwarranted unless a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Role of Semantics in Legal Expert Systems and Legal Reasoning.Ronald K. Stamper - 1991 - Ratio Juris 4 (2):219-244.
    The consensus among legal philosophers is probably that rule-based legal expert systems leave much to be desired as aids in legal decision-making. Why? What can we do about it? A bureaucrat administering some set of complex rules will ascertain the facts and apply the rules to them in order to discover their consequences for the case in hand. This process of deductive reasoning is characteristically bureaucratic.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Meaning and reference: Some Chomskian themes.Robert J. Stainton - 2006 - In Ernest Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language. Oxford University Press. pp. 913--940.
    This article introduces three arguments that share a single conclusion: that a comprehensive science of language cannot describe relations of semantic reference, i.e. word–world relations. Spelling this out, if there is to be a genuine science of linguistic meaning, then a theory of meaning cannot involve assigning external, real-world, objects to names, nor sets of external objects to predicates, nor truth values to sentences. Most of the article tries to explain and defend this broad conclusion. The article also presents, in (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Worlds, Models and Descriptions.John F. Sowa - 2006 - Studia Logica 84 (2):323-360.
    Since the pioneering work by Kripke and Montague, the term possible world has appeared in most theories of formal semantics for modal logics, natural languages, and knowledge-based systems. Yet that term obscures many questions about the relationships between the real world, various models of the world, and descriptions of those models in either formal languages or natural languages. Each step in that progression is an abstraction from the overwhelming complexity of the world. At the end, nothing is left but a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Indexical sense and reference.David Woodruff Smith - 1981 - Synthese 49 (1):101 - 127.
    This is a study of the epistemology of indexical reference, Or its foundation in the intentionality of the speaker's awareness of the referent. Where the referent is the object of the speaker's acquaintance on that occasion, The sense expressed is the generic content of that awareness. This, Indexical sense determines indexical reference, But indexical sense works by appeal to the context of the speaker's awareness of the referent. It is discussed how, By virtue of indexical sense, Indexical reference is rigid, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Logic and grammar.Hartley Slater - 2007 - Ratio 20 (2):206–218.
    I have written a number of articles recently that have a rather remarkable character. They all point out trivial grammatical facts that, at great cost, have not been respected in twentieth century Logic. A major continuous strand in my previous work, with this same character, I will first summarise, to locate the kind of fact that is involved. But then I shall present an overview of the more recent, and more varied points I have made, which demonstrate the far larger (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Compositionality, case, and the scope of auxiliaries.Muffy E. A. Siegel - 1987 - Linguistics and Philosophy 10 (1):53 - 75.
  • Choosing a unifying theory for cognitive development.Thomas R. Shultz - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):456-457.
  • Safety, the Preface Paradox and Possible Worlds Semantics.Michael J. Shaffer - 2019 - Axiomathes 29 (4):347-361.
    This paper contains an argument to the effect that possible worlds semantics renders semantic knowledge impossible, no matter what ontological interpretation is given to possible worlds. The essential contention made is that possible worlds semantic knowledge is unsafe and this is shown by a parallel with the preface paradox.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Situation Pronouns in Determiner Phrases.Florian Schwarz - 2012 - Natural Language Semantics 20 (4):431-475.
    It is commonly argued that natural language has the expressive power of quantifying over intensional entities, such as times, worlds, or situations. A standard way of modelling this assumes that there are unpronounced but syntactically represented variables of the corresponding type. Not all that much as has been said, however, about the exact syntactic location of these variables. Meanwhile, recent work has highlighted a number of problems that arise because the interpretive options for situation pronouns seem to be subject to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Quantifiers and Variables: Insights from Sign Language (ASL and LSF).Philippe Schlenker - 2011 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6:16.
  • Does the evolutionary perspective offer more than constraints?Wolfgang Schleidt - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):456-456.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a theory of anaphoric processing.Ivan A. Sag & Jorge Hankamer - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (3):325 - 345.
  • Intentional identity interpreted: A case study of the relations among quantifiers, pronouns, and propositional attitudes. [REVIEW]Esa Saarinen - 1978 - Linguistics and Philosophy 2 (2):151 - 223.
  • Entities for Analyzing Legal Relations.Richard E. Robinson - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (4):621-630.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantics and Discourse Representation.Richard Spencer-Smith - 1987 - Mind and Language 2 (1):1-26.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On interpreting pronouns.Barry Richards - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (3):287 - 324.
  • Ups and Downs in the theory of temporal reference.Uwe Reyle, Antje Rossdeutscher & Hans Kamp - 2007 - Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (5):565-635.
    This paper proposes a method for computing the temporal aspects of the interpretations of a variety of Germa sentences. The method is strictly modular in the sense that it allows each meaning-bearing sentence constituent to make its own, separate, contribution to the semantic representation of any sentence containing it. The semantic representation of a sentence is reached in several stages. First, an ‘initial semantic representation’ is constructed, using a syntactic analysis of the sentence as input. This initial representation is then (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • How human is SOAR?Roger W. Remington, Michael G. Shafto & Colleen M. Seifert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):455-455.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark