Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Evolution is not rational banking.Michael D. Zeiler - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):696-697.
  • Not all models are on the same level: Empirical law and hypothesis.Norio Yamamura - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):695-696.
  • Virtue Ethics is Empirically Adequate: A Defense of the Caps Response to Situationism.Ryan West - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (S1):79-111.
    According to situationists, the available empirical psychological data show that prevalent conceptions of virtue are ‘empirically inadequate.’ The charge is ambiguous. I begin by differentiating four families of empirical inadequacy charges, explaining the conceptual connections among the families, and showing how different situationists press different versions of the charges from each family. Then I explain how the empirical psychological model known as the ‘cognitive affective personality system,’ or ‘CAPS model,’ enables distinct responses to these varied charges. The CAPS response has (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior. [REVIEW]Peter B. M. Vranas - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (2):284-288.
    I agree with all four of the above theses, but I will argue that some of Doris’s arguments need improvement. I will deal only with arguments in defense of the thesis that situationism is true.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against Moral Character Evaluations: The Undetectability of Virtue and Vice.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2009 - The Journal of Ethics 13 (2-3):213 - 233.
    I defend the epistemic thesis that evaluations of people in terms of their moral character as good, bad, or intermediate are almost always epistemically unjustified. (1) Because most people are fragmented (they would behave deplorably in many and admirably in many other situations), one's prior probability that any given person is fragmented should be high. (2) Because one's information about specific people does not reliably distinguish those who are fragmented from those who are not, one's posterior probability that any given (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Evolution, behavior systems, and “self-control”: The fit between organism and test environment.William Timberlake - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):694-695.
  • Errors about errors: Virtue theory and trait attribution.Gopal Sreenivasan - 2002 - Mind 111 (441):47-68.
    This paper examines the implications of certain social psychological experiments for moral theory—specifically, for virtue theory. Gilbert Harman and John Doris have recently argued that the empirical evidence offered by ‘situationism’ demonstrates that there is no such thing as a character trait. I dispute this conclusion. My discussion focuses on the proper interpretation of the experimental data—the data themselves I grant for the sake of argument. I develop three criticisms of the anti-trait position. Of these, the central criticism concerns three (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Misinterpreting Mischel.Edmund J. S. Sonuga-Barke - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):693-694.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-control and the panda's thumb.Eliot Shimoff & A. Charles Catania - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):693-693.
  • The Normativity Challenge: Cultural Psychology Provides the Real Threat to Virtue Ethics.Jesse Prinz - 2009 - The Journal of Ethics 13 (2-3):117-144.
    Situationists argue that virtue ethics is empirically untenable, since traditional virtue ethicists postulate broad, efficacious character traits, and social psychology suggests that such traits do not exist. I argue that prominent philosophical replies to this challenge do not succeed. But cross-cultural research gives reason to postulate character traits, and this undermines the situationist critique. There is, however, another empirical challenge to virtue ethics that is harder to escape. Character traits are culturally informed, as are our ideals of what traits are (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • On observing the unobservable.Ovide F. Pomerleau & Cynthia S. Pomerleau - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):692-692.
  • Situationism, subjunctive hypocrisy and standing to blame.Adam Piovarchy - 2023 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 66 (4):514-538.
    Philosophers have argued that subjects who act wrongly in the situationist psychology experiments are morally responsible for their actions. This paper argues that though the obedient subjects in Milgram’s ‘Obedience to Authority’ experiments are blameworthy, since most of us would have acted in the same manner they did, it is inappropriate for most of us to blame them. On Todd’s ([2019]. “A Unified Account of the Moral Standing to Blame.” Noûs 53 (2): 347–374.) recent account of standing to blame, agents (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A non-reductive science of personality, character, and well-being must take the person's worldview into account.Artur Nilsson - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Does Habit Interference Explain Moral Failure?James Bernard Murphy - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (2):255-273.
    Social psychologists have performed many well-known experiments demonstrating that experimental subjects will perform in ways that are normatively inconsistent even across very similar situations. Situationist social psychologists and philosophers have often interpreted these findings to imply that most people lack general moral dispositions. These situationists have argued that our moral dispositions are at best narrowly local traits; they often describe our moral characters as fragmented. In this paper, I offer an alternative hypothesis for the same experimental results. I argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evolution and impulsiveness.Jay Moore - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):691-691.
  • Should Christians be Worried about Situationist Claims in Psychology and Philosophy?Christian B. Miller - 2016 - Faith and Philosophy 33 (1):48-73.
    The situationist movement in psychology and, more recently, in philosophy has been associated with a number of striking claims, including that most people do not have the moral virtues and vices, that any ethical theory which is wedded to such character traits is empirically inadequate, and that much of our behavior is causally influenced, to significant degrees, by psychological influences about which we are often unaware. Yet Christian philosophers have had virtually nothing to say about situationist claims. The goal of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the functions relating delay, reinforcer value, and behavior.James E. Mazur & R. J. Herrnstein - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):690-691.
  • Individual differences in workplace deviance and integrity as predictors of academic dishonesty.Gale M. Lucas & James Friedrich - 2005 - Ethics and Behavior 15 (1):15 – 35.
    Meta-analytic findings have suggested that individual differences are relatively weaker predictors of academic dishonesty than are situational factors. A robust literature on deviance correlates and workplace integrity testing, however, demonstrates that individual difference variables can be relatively strong predictors of a range of counterproductive work behaviors (CWBs). To the extent that academic cheating represents a kind of counterproductive behavior in the work role of "student", employment-type integrity measures should be strong predictors of academic dishonesty. Our results with a college student (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • On the origins of selves and self-control.C. Fergus Lowe & Pauline J. Home - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):689-690.
  • Working toward the big reinforcer: Integration.A. W. Logue - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):697-709.
  • Research on self-control: An integrating framework.A. W. Logue - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):665-679.
  • Functional characteristics of human self-control.Julius Kuhl - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):688-688.
  • Comments on Robert Adams, A theory of virtue: excellence in being for the good.Rachana Kamtekar - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 148 (1):147-158.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Personality and epistemology: Cognitive social learning theory as a philosophy of science.James W. Jones - 1989 - Zygon 24 (1):23-38.
    . Implicit in the cognitive social learning model of personality as articulated by Walter Mischel, Albert Bandura, and others, is an epistemology which emphasizes the activity of the mind in the construction of knowledge. Using Mischel's five person variables as an outline, the epistemic implications of this model of personality are developed and then illustrated by application to William James's typology of the religious personality and to the current debate over hermeneutic and empirical approaches to studying human behavior. This approach (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Self-restraint: A type of self-control in an approach-avoidance situation.Sumio Imada & Hiroshi Imada - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):687-688.
  • In delay there lies no plenty.Alasdair I. Houston & John M. McNamara - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):686-687.
  • The conflicting psychologies of self-control: A way out?John M. Hinson - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):685-686.
  • Indications of virtues in conscientiousness and its practice through continuous improvement.José Hernández & Ricardo Mateo - 2012 - Business Ethics: A European Review 21 (2):140-153.
    There is convergence among researchers of the ‘Big Five’ personality traits taxonomy, that the dimension of conscientiousness best explains differences in work performance. This research is a literature review on the interrelationship between certain traits of the conscientiousness dimension and human virtues, or character traits. It also analyzes whether or not it is rational to argue that the continuous improvement culture enhances the exercise of these character traits. The personal effort to develop one's conscientiousness enriches one's character or way of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Self-control in context.Leonard Green & Edwin B. Fisher - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):684-685.
  • Foraging for integration.Edmund Fantino & Ray Preston - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):683-684.
  • Perceptions and learning in self-control.Robert Eisenberger - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):682-683.
  • A social-cognitive approach to motivation and personality.Carol S. Dweck & Ellen L. Leggett - 1988 - Psychological Review 95 (2):256-273.
  • The Architecture of Personality.Daniel Cervone - 2004 - Psychological Review 111 (1):183-204.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • On the careful use of ecological models.Thomas Caraco - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):680-681.
  • On goals, perceptions, and self-control.Charles S. Carver - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):681-682.
  • Military Ethics and the Situationist Critique.Nathan L. Cartagena - 2017 - Journal of Military Ethics 16 (3-4):157-172.
    Many contributors to military ethics from diverse locations and philosophical perspectives maintain that virtues are central to martial theory and practice. Yet several contemporary philosophers and psychologists have recently challenged the empirical adequacy of this perspective. Their challenge is known as the situationist critique, a version of which asserts that: situational features rather than character traits such as virtues cause and explain human behavior, and ethical theories and development programs are empirically inadequate to the extent that they incorporate virtues. In (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Contextual Variability in Personality From Significant–Other Knowledge and Relational Selves.Susan M. Andersen, Rugile Tuskeviciute, Elizabeth Przybylinski, Janet N. Ahn & Joy H. Xu - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explaining Away Intuitions About Traits: Why Virtue Ethics Seems Plausible (Even if it Isn't).Mark Alfano - 2011 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2 (1):121-136.
    This article addresses the question whether we can know on the basis of folk intuitions that we have character traits. I answer in the negative, arguing that on any of the primary theories of knowledge, our intuitions about traits do not amount to knowledge. For instance, because we would attribute traits to one another regardless of whether we actually possessed such metaphysically robust dispositions, Nozickian sensitivity theory disqualifies our intuitions about traits from being knowledge. Yet we do think we know (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Matching is the integrating framework.George Ainslie - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):679-680.
  • The Psychology of Worldviews: Toward a Non-Reductive Science of Personality.Artur Nilsson - unknown
    Persons are not just mechanical systems of instinctual animalistic proclivities, but also language-producing, existentially aware creatures, whose experiences and actions are drenched in subjective meaning. To understand a human being as a person is to understand him or her as a rational system that wants, fears, hopes, believes, and in other ways imbues the world with meaning, rather than just a mechanical system that is subject to the same chains of cause and effect as other animals. But contemporary personality psychology (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Epistemic situationism and cognitive ability.John Turri - 2017 - In Mark Alfano & Abrol Fairweather (eds.), Epistemic Situationism. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 158-167.
    Leading virtue epistemologists defend the view that knowledge must proceed from intellectual virtue and they understand virtues either as refned character traits cultivated by the agent over time through deliberate effort, or as reliable cognitive abilities. Philosophical situationists argue that results from empirical psychology should make us doubt that we have either sort of epistemic virtue, thereby discrediting virtue epistemology’s empirical adequacy. I evaluate this situationist challenge and outline a successor to virtue epistemology: abilism . Abilism delivers all the main (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • From Virtue Epistemology to Abilism: Theoretical and Empirical Developments.John Turri - 2015 - In Christian B. Miller, Michael R. Furr, William Fleeson & Angela Knobel (eds.), Character: new directions from philosophy, psychology, and theology. Oxford: pp. 315-330.
    I review several theoretical and empirical developments relevant to assessing contemporary virtue epistemology’s theory of knowledge. What emerges is a leaner theory of knowledge that is more empirically adequate, better captures the ordinary conception of knowledge, and is ripe for cross-fertilization with cognitive science. I call this view abilism. Along the way I identify several topics for future research.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Situational Demand and Its Impact on Construct and Criterion Validity of a Personality Questionnaire: State and Trait, a Couple you just can’t Study Separately!Matthias Ziegler - unknown
    The present paper had four goals which all aimed at understanding more of the psychological process taking place when people intentionally distort their answers to a questionnaire. Moreover, possible causes for individual differences in responding to situational demand were investigated. Finally, it was explored whether there were any differences in the criterion validities of different conscientiousness scores. The results of the qualitative and the quantitative analyses show that the psychological process happening when people fake a questionnaire starts with the evaluation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark