Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. 2000 European Summer Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic. Logic Colloquium 2000.Carol Wood - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):82-163.
  • The counterparts to statements that are equivalent to the continuum hypothesis.Asger Törnquist & William Weiss - 2015 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 80 (4):1075-1090.
  • Σ1 2 and Π1 1 Mad Families.Asger Törnquist - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (4):1181-1182.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Σ12 and Π11 Mad Families.Asger Törnquist - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (4):1181-1182.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Madness in vector spaces.Iian B. Smythe - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (4):1590-1611.
    We consider maximal almost disjoint families of block subspaces of countable vector spaces, focusing on questions of their size and definability. We prove that the minimum infinite cardinality of such a family cannot be decided in ZFC and that the “spectrum” of cardinalities of mad families of subspaces can be made arbitrarily large, in analogy to results for mad families on ω. We apply the author’s local Ramsey theory for vector spaces [32] to give partial results concerning their definability.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Coanalytic ultrafilter bases.Jonathan Schilhan - 2022 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (3-4):567-581.
    We study the definability of ultrafilter bases on \ in the sense of descriptive set theory. As a main result we show that there is no coanalytic base for a Ramsey ultrafilter, while in L we can construct \ P-point and Q-point bases. We also show that the existence of a \ ultrafilter is equivalent to that of a \ ultrafilter base, for \. Moreover we introduce a Borel version of the classical ultrafilter number and make some observations.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Orthogonal families of real sequences.Arnold W. Miller & Juris Steprans - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (1):29-49.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zero-dimensional σ-homogeneous spaces.Andrea Medini & Zoltán Vidnyánszky - 2024 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 175 (1):103331.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Projective Hausdorff gaps.Yurii Khomskii - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (1-2):57-64.
    Todorčević (Fund Math 150(1):55–66, 1996) shows that there is no Hausdorff gap (A, B) if A is analytic. In this note we extend the result by showing that the assertion “there is no Hausdorff gap (A, B) if A is coanalytic” is equivalent to “there is no Hausdorff gap (A, B) if A is ${{\bf \it{\Sigma}}^{1}_{2}}$ ”, and equivalent to ${\forall r \; (\aleph_1^{L[r]}\,< \aleph_1)}$ . We also consider real-valued games corresponding to Hausdorff gaps, and show that ${\mathsf{AD}_\mathbb{R}}$ for pointclasses (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parametrized Ramsey theory of infinite block sequences of vectors.Jamal K. Kawach - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (8):102984.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Isomorphism types of maximal cofinitary groups.Bart Kastermans - 2009 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 15 (3):300-319.
    A cofinitary group is a subgroup of Sym(ℕ) where all nonidentity elements have finitely many fixed points. A maximal cofinitary group is a cofinitary group, maximal with respect to inclusion. We show that a maximal cofinitary group cannot have infinitely many orbits. We also show, using Martin's Axiom, that no further restrictions on the number of orbits can be obtained. We show that Martin's Axiom implies there exist locally finite maximal cofinitary groups. Finally we show that there exists a uniformly (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Analytic and coanalytic families of almost disjoint functions.Bart Kastermans, Juris Steprāns & Yi Zhang - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (4):1158-1172.
    If F ⊆ NN is an analytic family of pairwise eventually different functions then the following strong maximality condition fails: For any countable H ⊆ NN. no member of which is covered by finitely many functions from F, there is f ∈ F such that for all h ∈ H there are infinitely many integers k such that f(k) = h(k). However if V = L then there exists a coanalytic family of pairwise eventually different functions satisfying this strong maximality (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Complexity of Index Sets of Descriptive Set-Theoretic Notions.Reese Johnston & Dilip Raghavan - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (3):894-911.
    Descriptive set theory and computability theory are closely-related fields of logic; both are oriented around a notion of descriptive complexity. However, the two fields typically consider objects of very different sizes; computability theory is principally concerned with subsets of the naturals, while descriptive set theory is interested primarily in subsets of the reals. In this paper, we apply a generalization of computability theory, admissible recursion theory, to consider the relative complexity of notions that are of interest in descriptive set theory. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the non-existence of mad families.Haim Horowitz & Saharon Shelah - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (3-4):325-338.
    We show that the non-existence of mad families is equiconsistent with \, answering an old question of Mathias. We also consider the above result in the general context of maximal independent sets in Borel graphs, and we construct a Borel graph G such that \ “there is no maximal independent set in G” is equiconsistent with \ “there exists an inaccessible cardinal”.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Borel maximal eventually different family.Haim Horowitz & Saharon Shelah - forthcoming - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Projective mad families.Sy-David Friedman & Lyubomyr Zdomskyy - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (12):1581-1587.
    Using almost disjoint coding we prove the consistency of the existence of a definable ω-mad family of infinite subsets of ω together with.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Definable MAD families and forcing axioms.Vera Fischer, David Schrittesser & Thilo Weinert - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (5):102909.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Co-analytic mad families and definable wellorders.Vera Fischer, Sy David Friedman & Yurii Khomskii - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (7-8):809-822.
    We show that the existence of a ${\Pi^1_1}$ -definable mad family is consistent with the existence of a ${\Delta^{1}_{3}}$ -definable well-order of the reals and ${\mathfrak{b}=\mathfrak{c}=\aleph_3}$.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cohen preservation and independence.Vera Fischer & Corey Bacal Switzer - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (8):103291.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A co-analytic maximal set of orthogonal measures.Vera Fischer & Asger Törnquist - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (4):1403-1414.
    We prove that if V = L then there is a $\Pi _{1}^{1}$ maximal orthogonal (i.e., mutually singular) set of measures on Cantor space. This provides a natural counterpoint to the well-known theorem of Preiss and Rataj [16] that no analytic set of measures can be maximal orthogonal.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A co-analytic Cohen-indestructible maximal cofinitary group.Vera Fischer, David Schrittesser & Asger Törnquist - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (2):629-647.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Maximal Chains in the Turing Degrees.C. T. Chong & Liang Yu - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (4):1219 - 1227.
    We study the problem of existence of maximal chains in the Turing degrees. We show that: 1. ZF+DC+"There exists no maximal chain in the Turing degrees" is equiconsistent with ZFC+"There exists an inaccessible cardinal"; 2. For all a ∈ 2ω.(ω₁)L[a] = ω₁ if and only if there exists a $\Pi _{1}^{1}[a]$ maximal chain in the Turing degrees. As a corollary, ZFC + "There exists an inaccessible cardinal" is equiconsistent with ZFC + "There is no (bold face) $\utilde{\Pi}{}_{1}^{1}$ maximal chain of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Every zero-dimensional homogeneous space is strongly homogeneous under determinacy.Raphaël Carroy, Andrea Medini & Sandra Müller - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 20 (3):2050015.
    All spaces are assumed to be separable and metrizable. We show that, assuming the Axiom of Determinacy, every zero-dimensional homogeneous space is strongly homogeneous (i.e. all its non-empty clopen subspaces are homeomorphic), with the trivial exception of locally compact spaces. In fact, we obtain a more general result on the uniqueness of zero-dimensional homogeneous spaces which generate a given Wadge class. This extends work of van Engelen (who obtained the corresponding results for Borel spaces), complements a result of van Douwen, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Regularity properties for dominating projective sets.Jörg Brendle, Greg Hjorth & Otmar Spinas - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 72 (3):291-307.
    We show that every dominating analytic set in the Baire space has a dominating closed subset. This improves a theorem of Spinas [15] saying that every dominating analytic set contains the branches of a uniform tree, i.e. a superperfect tree with the property that for every splitnode all the successor splitnodes have the same length. In [15], a subset of the Baire space is called u-regular if either it is not dominating or it contains the branches of a uniform tree, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Mad Families Constructed from Perfect Almost Disjoint Families.Jörg Brendle & Yurii Khomskii - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (4):1164-1180.
  • Projective well orders and coanalytic witnesses.Jeffrey Bergfalk, Vera Fischer & Corey Bacal Switzer - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (8):103135.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Parameterized partition relations on the real numbers.Joan Bagaria & Carlos A. Di Prisco - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (2):201-226.
    We consider several kinds of partition relations on the set ${\mathbb{R}}$ of real numbers and its powers, as well as their parameterizations with the set ${[\mathbb{N}]^{\mathbb{N}}}$ of all infinite sets of natural numbers, and show that they hold in some models of set theory. The proofs use generic absoluteness, that is, absoluteness under the required forcing extensions. We show that Solovay models are absolute under those forcing extensions, which yields, for instance, that in these models for every well ordered partition (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations