Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The vagaries of paraphrase: a reply to Holton on the counting problem.Ian Rumfitt - 1996 - Analysis 56 (4):246-250.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ways of meaning.Mark Platts - 1979 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (1):141-156.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Propositions as Made of Words.Gary Kemp - 2022 - Erkenntnis 89 (2):591-606.
    I argue that the principal roles standardly envisaged for abstract propositions can be discharged to the sentences themselves (and similarly for the meanings or senses of words). I discuss: (1) Cognitive Value: Hesperus-Phosphorus; (2) Indirect Sense and Propositional Attitudes; (3) the Paradox of Analysis; (4) the Picture Theory of the Tractatus; (5) Syntactical Diagrams and Meaning; (6) Quantifying-in. (7) Patterns of Use. I end with comparisons with related views of the territory.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Davidson, McFetridge, and the counting problem.R. Holton - 1996 - Analysis 56 (1):46-50.
  • On speaking thus: The semantics of indirect discourse.Jane Heal - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 51 (205):433-454.
    Indexical predication is possible as well as the more familiar indexical reference. ‘My curtains are coloured thus’ describes my curtains. The indexical predicate expression it contains stands to possible non‐indexical replacements as a referring indexical does to possible non‐indexical replacements , in that it calls upon the context of utterance to fix its semantic contribution to the whole. Indexical predication is the natural resource to call upon in talk about skilful human performances, where we exhibit considerable know‐how but little explicit (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How should we revise the paratactic theory?Keith Frankish - 1996 - Analysis 56 (4):251–262.
    This paper takes another look at Davidson's paratactic theory of indirect discourse and evaluates some revisions to it, proposed recently by Ian Rumfitt (Mind, 1993). Davidson's original version of the theory – according to which indirect speech reports refer to token utterances – has a problem dealing with ambiguity. Rumfitt suggests that we can solve this problem by supposing that the immediate objects of verbs in indirect speech are token representations of disambiguated LF tree-structures. I argue that this proposal is (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On a Davidsonian objection to minimalism.J. Dodd - 1997 - Analysis 57 (4):267-272.
    Two features of Paul Horwich's minimalist conception of truth (1990) make it stand out from the deflationary crowd. First, Horwich takes propositions to be the primary vehicles of truth (1990: 17-18, Ch. 6). Second, he claims that an explicit definition of truth applicable to propositions cannot be given (1990: 26-31), and hence that the meaning of 'true' can only be determined by our disposition to assent to the infinitely many (non-paradoxical) instances of the following schema: (E) The proposition that p (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Countering the counting problem: a reply to Holton.J. Dodd - 1996 - Analysis 56 (4):239-245.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Indirect reports as language games.Alessandro Capone - 2012 - Pragmatics and Cognition 20 (3):593-613.
    In this chapter I deal with indirect reports in terms of language games. I try to make connections between the theory of language games and the theory of indirect reports, in the light of the issue of clues and cues. Indirect reports are based on an interplay of voices. The voice of the reporter must allow hearers to ‘reconstruct’ the voice of the reported speaker. Ideally, it must be possible to separate the reporter’s voice from that of the reported speaker. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Ways of meaning.Steven E. Boër - 1980 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (1):141-156.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • "Ways of Meaning" by Mark Platts. [REVIEW]Steven E. Boër - 1980 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (1):141-156.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (Non-)Conceptual Representation of Meaning in Utterance Comprehension.Anders Nes - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    Many views of utterance comprehension agree that understanding an utterance involves knowing, believing, perceiving, or, anyhow, mentally representing the utterance to mean such-and-such. They include cognitivist as well as many perceptualist views; I give them the generic label ‘representationalist’. Representationalist views have been criticized for placing an undue metasemantic demand on utterance comprehension, viz. that speakers be able to represent meaning as meaning. Critics have adverted to young speakers, say about the age of three, who do comprehend many utterances but (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark