Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The emergence of group cognition.Georg Theiner & Tim O'Connor - 2010 - In Antonella Corradini & Timothy O'Connor (eds.), Emergence in science and philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 6--78.
    What drives much of the current philosophical interest in the idea of group cognition is its appeal to the manifestation of psychological properties—understood broadly to include states, processes, and dispositions—that are in some important yet elusive sense emergent with respect to the minds of individual group members. Our goal in this paper is to address a set of related, conditional questions: If human mentality is real yet emergent in a modest metaphysical sense only, then: (i) What would it mean for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Weirdness of the World.Eric Schwitzgebel - 2024 - Princeton University Press.
    How all philosophical explanations of human consciousness and the fundamental structure of the cosmos are bizarre—and why that’s a good thing Do we live inside a simulated reality or a pocket universe embedded in a larger structure about which we know virtually nothing? Is consciousness a purely physical matter, or might it require something extra, something nonphysical? According to the philosopher Eric Schwitzgebel, it’s hard to say. In The Weirdness of the World, Schwitzgebel argues that the answers to these fundamental (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘The dangers of this atmosphere’: a Quaker connection in the Tavistock Clinic’s development.Sebastian Kraemer - 2011 - History of the Human Sciences 24 (2):82-102.
    During the Second World War, through innovations in officer selection and group therapy, the army psychiatrists John Rickman and Wilfred Bion changed our understanding of leadership. They showed how soldiers under stress could develop real authority through their attentiveness to each other. From contrasting experiences 25 years earlier each had seen how people in groups are moved by elemental forces that undermine judgement and thought. This article arose from my experiences as a trainee at the Tavistock Clinic, where the method (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Group Mind.Bryce Huebner - 2016 - In Justin Sytsma & Wesley Buckwalter (eds.), A Companion to Experimental Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley. pp. 292–305.
    This chapter examines the recent work in psychology and experimental philosophy that has targeted the commonsense understanding of group minds. It begins by setting up the conceptual and empirical terrain on which claims about the group mind in commonsense psychology have been constructed. The chapter explains an analysis of the cross‐cultural data, which suggest a greater willingness to ascribe collective mentality in East Asian cultures. It addresses that the different strands of data together support the claim that commonsense psychology is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is Collective Agency a Coherent Idea? Considerations from the Enactive Theory of Agency.Mog Stapleton & Tom Froese - 1st ed. 2015 - In Catrin Misselhorn (ed.), Collective Agency and Cooperation in Natural and Artificial Systems. Springer Verlag. pp. 219-236.
    Whether collective agency is a coherent concept depends on the theory of agency that we choose to adopt. We argue that the enactive theory of agency developed by Barandiaran, Di Paolo and Rohde (2009) provides a principled way of grounding agency in biological organisms. However the importance of biological embodiment for the enactive approach might lead one to be skeptical as to whether artificial systems or collectives of individuals could instantiate genuine agency. To explore this issue we contrast the concept (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Dialogues in Argumentation.Von Burg Ron - 2016 - Windsor: University of Windsor.
    This volume focuses on dialogue and argumentation in contexts which are marked by truculence and discord. The contributors include well known argumentation scholars who discuss the issues this raises from the point of view of a variety of disciplines and points of view. The authors seek to address theoretically challenging issues in a way that is relevant to both the theory and the practice of argument. The collection brings together selected essays from the 2006 11th Wake Forest University Biennial Argumentation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • We in Me or Me in We? Collective Intentionality and Selfhood.Dan Zahavi - 2021 - Journal of Social Ontology 7 (1):1-20.
    The article takes issue with the proposal that dominant accounts of collective intentionality suffer from an individualist bias and that one should instead reverse the order of explanation and give primacy to the we and the community. It discusses different versions of the community first view and argues that they fail because they operate with too simplistic a conception of what it means to be a self and misunderstand what it means to be (part of) a we. In presenting this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The maintenance of behavioral diversity in human societies.Christopher Wills - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):638-639.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reintroducing group selection to the human behavioral sciences.David Sloan Wilson & Elliott Sober - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):585-608.
    In both biology and the human sciences, social groups are sometimes treated as adaptive units whose organization cannot be reduced to individual interactions. This group-level view is opposed by a more individualistic one that treats social organization as a byproduct of self-interest. According to biologists, group-level adaptations can evolve only by a process of natural selection at the group level. Most biologists rejected group selection as an important evolutionary force during the 1960s and 1970s but a positive literature began to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Group selection: The theory replaces the bogey man.David Sloan Wilson & Elliott Sober - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):639-654.
    In both biology and the human sciences, social groups are sometimes treated as adaptive units whose organization cannot be reduced to individual interactions. This group-level view is opposed by a more individualistic one that treats social organization as a byproduct of self-interest. According to biologists, group-level adaptations can evolve only by a process of natural selection at the group level. Most biologists rejected group selection as an important evolutionary force during the 1960s and 1970s but a positive literature began to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Group-level cognition.Robert A. Wilson - 2001 - Philosophy of Science 68 (3):S262-S273.
    David Sloan Wilson has recently revived the idea of a group mind as an application of group selectionist thinking to cognition. Central to my discussion of this idea is the distinction between the claim that groups have a psychology and what I call the social manifestation thesis-a thesis about the psychology of individuals. Contemporary work on this topic has confused these two theses. My discussion also points to research questions and issues that Wilson's work raises, as well as their connection (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Accountability Accentuates Interindividual-Intergroup Discontinuity by Enforcing Parochialism.Tim Wildschut, Femke van Horen & Claire Hart - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The “One Mind, Two Aspects” Model of the Self: The Self Model and Self-Cultivation Theory of Chinese Buddhism.Kai Wang - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Constructing a self model with universal cultural adaptability is a common concern of cultural psychologists. These models can be divided into two types: one is the self model based on Western culture, represented by the self theory of Marsh, Cooley, Fitts, etc.; the other is the non-self model based on Eastern culture, represented by the Mandela model of Hwang Kwang Kuo and the Taiji model of Zhen Dong Wang. However, these models do not fully explain the self structure and development (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Vehicles all the way down?Nicholas S. Thompson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):638-638.
  • Semantics, theory, and methodological individualism in the group-selection controversy.Eric Alden Smith - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):636-637.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fostering Collective Growth and Vitality Following Acts of Moral Courage: A General System, Relational Psychodynamic Perspective.Sheldene Simola - 2018 - Journal of Business Ethics 148 (1):169-182.
    The purpose of this article is to explore a critical paradox related to the expression of moral courage in organizations, which is that although morally courageous acts are aimed at fostering collective growth, vitality, and virtue, their initial result is typically one of collective unease, preoccupation, or lapse, reflected in the social ostracism and censure of the courageous member and message. Therefore, this article addresses the questions of why many organizational groups suffer stagnation or decline rather than growth and vitality (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Adaptation and natural selection: A new look at some old ideas.Jeffry A. Simpson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):634-636.
  • If materialism is true, the United States is probably conscious.Eric Schwitzgebel - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (7):1697-1721.
    If you’re a materialist, you probably think that rabbits are conscious. And you ought to think that. After all, rabbits are a lot like us, biologically and neurophysiologically. If you’re a materialist, you probably also think that conscious experience would be present in a wide range of naturally-evolved alien beings behaviorally very similar to us even if they are physiologically very different. And you ought to think that. After all, to deny it seems insupportable Earthly chauvinism. But a materialist who (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Insects, instincts and boundary work in early social psychology.Diane M. Rodgers - 2013 - History of the Human Sciences 26 (1):68-89.
    Insects factored as ‘symbols of instinct’, necessary as a rhetorical device in the boundary work of early social psychology. They were symbolically used to draw a dividing line between humans and animals, clarifying views on instinct and consciousness. These debates were also waged to determine if social psychology was a subfield of sociology or psychology. The exchange between psychologist James Mark Baldwin and sociologist Charles Abram Ellwood exemplifies this particular aspect of boundary work. After providing a general background of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nongenetic and non-Darwinian evolution.Anatol Rapoport - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):634-634.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A multi-agent based framework for the simulation of human and social behaviors during emergency evacuations.Xiaoshan Pan, Charles S. Han, Ken Dauber & Kincho H. Law - 2007 - AI and Society 22 (2):113-132.
    Many computational tools for the simulation and design of emergency evacuation and egress are now available. However, due to the scarcity of human and social behavioral data, these computational tools rely on assumptions that have been found inconsistent or unrealistic. This paper presents a multi-agent based framework for simulating human and social behavior during emergency evacuation. A prototype system has been developed, which is able to demonstrate some emergent behaviors, such as competitive, queuing, and herding behaviors. For illustration, an example (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why is group selection such a problem?Randolph M. Nesse - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):633-634.
  • Hominids, coalitions, and weapons: Not vehicles.Jim Moore - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):632-632.
  • On therapeutic authority: psychoanalytical expertise under advanced liberalism.Peter Miller & Nikolas Rose - 1994 - History of the Human Sciences 7 (3):29-64.
  • Beyond shared fate: Group-selected mechanisms for cooperation and competition in fuzzy, fluid vehicles.Geoffrey F. Miller - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):630-631.
  • Group evolutionary strategies: Dimensions and mechanisms.Kevin MacDonald - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):629-630.
  • Rx: Distinguish group selection from group adaptation.Elisabeth A. Lloyd - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):628-629.
    I admire Wilson & Sober's (W & S's) aim, to alert social scientists that group selection has risen from the ashqs, and to explicate its relevance to the behavioral sciences. Group selection has beenwidely misunderstood; furthermore, both authors have been instrumental in illuminating conceptual problems surrounding higher-level selection. Still, I find that this target article muddies the waters, primarily through its shifting and confused definition of a "vehicle" of selection. The fundamental problem is an ambiguity in the definition of "adaptation." (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychology and anthropology: the British experience.Adam Kuper - 1990 - History of the Human Sciences 3 (3):397-413.
  • ‘Common Purpose’: The Crowd and the Public.Ulrike Kistner - 2015 - Law and Critique 26 (1):27-43.
    The legal doctrine of ‘common purpose’ in South African criminal law considers all parties liable who have been in implicit or explicit agreement to commit an unlawful act, and associated with each other for that purpose, even if the consequential act has been carried out by one of them. It relieves the prosecution of proving the causal link between the conduct of an individual member of a group acting in common purpose, and the ultimate consequence caused by the action of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Different vehicles for group selection in humans.Michael E. Hyland - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):628-628.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Taking vechicles seriously.David L. Hull - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):627-628.
  • What Does the Nation of China Think About Phenomenal States?Bryce Huebner, Michael Bruno & Hagop Sarkissian - 2010 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2):225-243.
    Critics of functionalism about the mind often rely on the intuition that collectivities cannot be conscious in motivating their positions. In this paper, we consider the merits of appealing to the intuition that there is nothing that it’s like to be a collectivity. We demonstrate that collective mentality is not an affront to commonsense, and we report evidence that demonstrates that the intuition that there is nothing that it’s like to be a collectivity is, to some extent, culturally specific rather (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Groups as vehicles and replicators: The problem of group-level adaptation.Kent E. Holsinger - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):626-627.
  • Empirically equivalent theories.Harmon R. Holcomb - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):625-626.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reconstructing the real unit of selection.Adolf Heschl - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):624-625.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Replicators and vehicles? Or developmental systems?P. E. Griffiths & R. D. Gray - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):623-624.
  • Putting the cart back behind the horse: Group selection does not require that groups be “organisms”.Todd A. Grantham - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):622-623.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contextual analysis and group selection.Charles J. Goodnight - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):622-622.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Me, you, and us: Distinguishing “egoism,” “altruism,” and “groupism”.Margaret Gilbert - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):621-622.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Group selection and “genuine” altruism.Robert H. Frank - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):620-621.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some philosophical implications of the rehabilitation of group selection.John Dupré - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):619-620.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Subtle ways of shifting the balance in favor of between-group selection.Lee Alan Dugatkin - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):618-619.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • E pluribus unum?Daniel C. Dennett - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):617-618.
    W&S correctly ask if groups can be like individuals in the harmony and cooperation of their parts, but in their answer, they ignore the importance of the difference between genetically related and unrelated components, and also misconstrue the import of the Hutterites.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Burying the vehicle.Richard Dawkins - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):616-617.
  • In praise of replicators.James F. Crow - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):616-616.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Group selection's new clothes.Lee Cronk - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):615-616.
  • Unnecessary competition requirement makes group selection harder to demonstrate.F. T. Cloak - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):614-615.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ambivalently held group-optimizing predispositions.Donald T. Campbell & John B. Gatewood - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):614-614.
  • Group selection and the group mind in science.Gordon M. Burghardt - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):613-613.
  • The consequences of group selection in a domain without genetic input: Culture.C. Loring Brace - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):611-612.