Switch to: References

Citations of:

An Outline of Psychology

Sigaud Press (2007)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Meaning and Emotion: The Extended Gricean Model and What Emotional Signs Mean.Constant Bonard - 2021 - Dissertation, University of Geneva and University of Antwerp
    This dissertation may be divided into two parts. The first part is about the Extended Gricean Model of information transmission. This model, introduced here, is meant to better explain how humans communicate and understand each other. It has been developed to apply to cases that were left unexplained by the two main models of communication found in contemporary philosophy and linguistics, i.e. the Gricean (pragmatic) model and the code (semantic) model. In particular, I show that these latter two models cannot (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Emotion and Language in Philosophy.Constant Bonard - 2023 - In Gesine Lenore Schiewer, Jeanette Altarriba & Bee Chin Ng (eds.), Emotion and Language. An International Handbook.
    In this chapter, we start by spelling out three important features that distinguish expressives—utterances that express emotions and other affects—from descriptives, including those that describe emotions (Section 1). Drawing on recent insights from the philosophy of emotion and value (2), we show how these three features derive from the nature of affects, concentrating on emotions (3). We then spell out how theories of non-natural meaning and communication in the philosophy of language allow claims that expressives inherit their meaning from specificities (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reconstructing the Past: A Century of Ideas About Emotion in Psychology.Maria Gendron & Lisa Feldman Barrett - 2009 - Emotion Review 1 (4):316.
    Within the discipline of psychology, the conventional history outlines the development of two fundamental approaches to the scientific study of emotion—“basic emotion” and “appraisal” traditions. In this article, we outline the development of a third approach to emotion that exists in the psychological literature—the “psychological constructionist” tradition. In the process, we discuss a number of works that have virtually disappeared from the citation trail in psychological discussions of emotion. We also correct some misconceptions about early sources, such as work by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Reconstructing the Past: A Century of Ideas About Emotion in Psychology.Maria Gendron & Lisa Feldman Barrett - 2009 - Emotion Review 1 (4):316-339.
    Within the discipline of psychology, the conventional history outlines the development of two fundamental approaches to the scientific study of emotion—“basic emotion” and “appraisal” traditions. In this article, we outline the development of a third approach to emotion that exists in the psychological literature—the “psychological constructionist” tradition. In the process, we discuss a number of works that have virtually disappeared from the citation trail in psychological discussions of emotion. We also correct some misconceptions about early sources, such as work by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Emotion Experience, Rational Action, and Self-Knowledge.John A. Lambie - 2009 - Emotion Review 1 (3):272-280.
    This article examines the role of emotion experience in both rational action and self-knowledge. A key distinction is made between emotion experiences of which we are unaware, and those of which we are aware. The former motivate action and color our view of the world, but they do not do so in a rational way, and their nonreflective nature obscures self-understanding. The article provides arguments and evidence to support the view that emotion experiences contribute to rational action only if one (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Is neuroethology wise?J. Z. Young - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):403-403.
  • Ethology and neuroethology: Easy accessibility has been and still is important.Edgar T. Walters - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):402-403.
  • The Role of the Visual Arts in the Enhancing the Learning Process.Christopher W. Tyler & Lora T. Likova - 2012 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 6.
  • Getting Bodily Feelings Into Emotional Experience in the Right Way.Fabrice Teroni & Julien A. Deonna - 2017 - Emotion Review 9 (1):55-63.
    We argue that the main objections against two central tenets of a Jamesian account of the emotions, i.e. that (1) different types of emotions are associated with specific types of bodily feelings (Specificity), and that (2) emotions are constituted by patterns of bodily feeling (Constitution), do not succeed. In the first part, we argue that several reasons adduced against Specifity, including one inspired by Schachter and Singer’s work, are unconvincing. In the second part, we argue that Constitution, too, can withstand (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The proper domain of neuroethology.Horst D. Steklis - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):401-402.
  • Keep the scope of neuroethology broad.James A. Simmons - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):400-401.
  • Neuroethology—how exclusive a club?Allen I. Selverston - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):399-400.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Points of congruence between ethology and neuroscience.Wolfgang M. Schleidt - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):398-399.
  • Resurrecting Lorenz's hydraulic model: Phlogiston explained by quantum mechanics.C. H. F. Rowell - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):397-398.
  • Emotions at the Service of Cultural Construction.Bernard Rimé - 2019 - Emotion Review 12 (2):65-78.
    Emotions signal flaws in the person’s anticipation systems, or in other words, in aspects of models of how the world works. As these models are essentially shared in society, emotional challenges e...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • More on James and the Physical Basis of Emotion.Rainer Reisenzein & Achim Stephan - 2014 - Emotion Review 6 (1):35-46.
    We first present a reconstruction of James’s theory of emotion (JATE) and then argue for four theses: (a) Despite constructivist elements, James’s views are overall in line with basic emotions theory. (b) JATE does not exclude an influence of emotion on intentional action even in its original formulation; nevertheless, this influence is quite limited. It seems possible, however, to repair this problem of the theory. (c) Cannon’s theory of emotion is a centralized version of JATE that inherits from the latter (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Arnold's theory of emotion in historical perspective.Rainer Reisenzein - 2006 - Cognition and Emotion 20 (7):920-951.
    Magda B. Arnold's theory of emotion is examined from three historical viewpoints. First, I look backward from Arnold to precursors of her theory of emotion in 19th century introspectionist psychology and in classical evolutionary psychology. I try to show that Arnold can be regarded as belonging intellectually to the cognitive tradition of emotion theorising that originated in Brentano and his students, and that she was also significantly influenced by McDougall's evolutionary view of emotion. Second, I look forward from Arnold to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A biological approach to sociological functionalism.Vernon Pratt - 1975 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 18 (4):371 – 389.
    The rationale for the common rejection of classical societal functionalism is that it entails treating a society as an intelligent purposer, capable of directing its own internal organization in furtherance of survival. But a more acceptable alternative account of the origins of a society's functional organization is conceivable: the individual unconsciously recognizes the needs of his group and directs his behaviour so that they are met. The plausibility of this explanation hangs on whether selection between groups occurs to any significant (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The relation of inner experience and overt behaviour.W. M. O'Neil - 1949 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):27-45.
  • Purposivism.W. M. O'Neil - 1947 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 25 (3):152 – 173.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Goals of action and emotional reasons for action. A modern version of the theory of ultimate psychological hedonism.Ulrich Mees & Annette Schmitt - 2008 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 38 (2):157–178.
    In this paper we present a modern version of the classic theory of “ultimate psychological hedonism” . As does the UPH, our two-dimensional model of metatelic orientations also postulates a fundamentally hedonistic motivation for any human action. However, it makes a distinction between “telic” or content-based goals of actions and “metatelic” or emotional reasons for actions. In our view, only the emotional reasons for action, but not the goals of action, conform to the UPH. After outlining our model, we will (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Gestalt Psychology.Maxwell Garnett - 1943 - Philosophy 18 (69):37 - 49.
    The aim of psychology is first of all to describe how we think, or the flow of our consciousness, and then to sum up the facts in terms of principles, generalizations, or “laws” which “govern” our thinking. These laws must enable us to foretell what a man will think and how he will act when we know his environment and the state of his thought at any given moment, provided that no unforeseeable exercise of free will intervenes. Psychology has also (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ethology of neuroethology.Hubert Markl - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):396-397.
  • Why “consciousness” means what it does.Neil C. Manson - 2011 - Metaphilosophy 42 (1-2):98-117.
    Abstract: “Consciousness” seems to be a polysemic, ambiguous, term. Because of this, theorists have sought to distinguish the different kinds of phenomena that “consciousness” denotes, leading to a proliferation of terms for different kinds of consciousness. However, some philosophers—univocalists about consciousness—argue that “consciousness” is not polysemic or ambiguous. By drawing upon the history of philosophy and psychology, and some resources from semantic theory, univocalism about consciousness is shown to be implausible. This finding is important, for if we accept the univocalist (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Neuroethology: Not losing sight of behaviour.Aubrey Manning - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):395-396.
  • We are making good progress in the neural analysis of behaviour.David L. Macmillan - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):395-395.
  • The squishy revisited: A call for ethological affirmative action.Janet L. Leonard & Ken Lukowiak - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):394-394.
  • They are really complex when you get to know them.Irving Kupfermann - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):393-394.
  • The Sphex story: How the cognitive sciences kept repeating an old and questionable anecdote.Fred Keijzer - 2013 - Philosophical Psychology 26 (4):502-519.
    The Sphex story is an anecdote about a female digger wasp that at first sight seems to act quite intelligently, but subsequently is shown to be a mere automaton that can be made to repeat herself endlessly. Dennett and Hofstadter made this story well known and widely influential within the cognitive sciences, where it is regularly used as evidence that insect behavior is highly rigid. The present paper discusses the origin and subsequent empirical investigation of the repetition reported in the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Vertebrate neuroethology: Doomed from the start?David J. Ingle - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):392-393.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuroethology, according to Hoyle.Franz Huber - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):391-392.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Do discrete emotions exist?Yang-Ming Huang, Maria Gendron & Lisa Feldman Barrett - 2009 - Philosophical Psychology 22 (4):427-437.
    In various guises (usually referred to as the “basic emotion” or “discrete emotion” approach), scientists and philosophers have long argued that certain categories of emotion are natural kinds. In a recent paper, Colombetti (2009) proposed yet another natural kind account, and in so doing, characterized and critiqued psychological constructionist approaches to emotion, including our own Conceptual Act Model. In this commentary, we briefly address three topics raised by Columbetti. First, we correct several common misperceptions about the discrete emotion approach to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The scope of neuroethology.Graham Hoyle - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):367.
  • Neuroethology: To be, or not to be?Graham Hoyle - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):403-412.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ethology has progressed.Robert A. Hinde - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):391-391.
  • Can the aims of neuroethology be selective, while avoiding exclusivity?D. M. Guthrie - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):390-391.
  • Neuroethology and theoretical neurobiology.Stephen Grossberg - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):388-390.
  • Neuroethology according to Hoyle.Russell D. Fernald - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):387-388.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hoyle's new view of neuroethology: Limited and restrictive.J. P. Ewert - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):386-387.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuroethology or motorethology?Joachim Erber - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):386-386.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Disregarding vertebrates is neither useful nor necessary.Günter Ehret - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):385-386.
  • Can neuroethologists be led?Fred Delcomyn - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):385.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuroethology: Why put it in a straitjacket?Jackson Davis - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):384.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Difficulties and relevance of a neuroethological approach to neurobiology.F. Clarac - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):383.
  • Neuroethology: In defense of open range; don't fence me in.Theodore H. Bullock - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):383.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neuroethology: An overnarrow definition can become a source of dogmatism.Ulrich Bässler - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):382.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Instinct Concept of the Early Konrad Lorenz.Ingo Brigandt - 2005 - Journal of the History of Biology 38 (3):571-608.
    Peculiar to Konrad Lorenz’s view of instinctive behavior is his strong innate-learned dichotomy. He claimed that there are neither ontogenetic nor phylogenetic transitions between instinctive and experience-based behavior components, thus contradicting all former accounts of instinct. The present study discusses how Lorenz came to hold this controversial position by examining the history of Lorenz’s early theoretical development in the crucial period from 1931 to 1937, taking relevant influences into account. Lorenz’s intellectual development is viewed as being guided by four theoretical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Remarks on Receiving the Covey Award.Margaret A. Boden - 2013 - Philosophy and Technology 26 (3):333-339.
  • Flow diagrams and hydraulic models.Patrick Bateson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):382.
  • Neuroethology: A call for less exclusivity and more theory.Michael A. Arbib - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):381.