Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Philosophy of Leibniz

Philosophical Review 99 (4):613-629 (1990)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Leibniz, Whitehead, and the metaphysics of causation.Pierfrancesco Basile - 2009 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    This book introduces the reader to Whitehead’s complex and often misunderstood metaphysics by showing that it deals with questions about the nature of causation originally raised by the philosophy of Leibniz. Whitehead’s philosophy is an attempt at rehabilitating Leibniz’s theory of monads by recasting it in terms of novel ontological categories.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Zur diskussion.[author unknown] - 1999 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 81 (3):316-328.
    According to one of Leibniz’s theories of contingency a proposition is contingent if and only if it cannot be proved in a finite number of steps. It has been argued that this faces the Problem of Lucky Proof, namely that we could begin by analysing the concept ‘Peter’ by saying that ‘Peter is a denier of Christ and …’, thereby having proved the proposition ‘Peter denies Christ’ in a finite number of steps. It also faces a more general but related (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ontologický status ideálního prostoru u Leibnize.Kateřina Lochmanová - 2019 - Pro-Fil 20 (2):30.
    Studie se věnuje otázce po ontologickém statusu ideálního, potažmo fenomenálního prostoru v pojetí Gottfrieda Wilhelma Leibnize. Nejprve bude ujasněno, v jakém smyslu lze podle Leibnize za prostor v pravém slova smyslu považovat primárně pouze prostor ideální, sekundárně však rovněž prostor fenomenální. Posléze se vymezím zejména vůči takovým interpretacím leibnizovského ideálního prostoru, které v něm spatřují předzvěst prostoru kantovského. Leibnizův ideální, matematický prostor zde totiž bude přirovnán spíše k prostoru suárezovskému, případně hobbesovskému, nikoli však kantovskému.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the (Im)Possibility of Global Norms in a Divided World: Lessons from the Seventeenth Century.Ekaterina Yahyaoui Krivenko - 2020 - Jus Cogens 2 (1):57-74.
    In order to develop a deep and detailed reflection on global norms, international law scholars need to pay more attention to insights supplied by the discussions on the philosophical problem of universals. Using the examples of the discussion on universals in Leibniz and Hobbes, the paper demonstrates the importance of the philosophical problem of universals to discussions on the possibility of global norms. In particular, the comparative study of Leibniz and Hobbes demonstrates that a world divided in states mostly presupposes (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three moments in the theory of definition or analysis: Its possibility, its aim or aims, and its limit or terminus.David Wiggins - 2007 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 107 (1pt1):73-109.
    The reflections recorded in this paper arise from three moments in the theory of definition and of conceptual analysis. The moments are: Frege’s review of Husserl’s Philosophy of Arithmetic, the discussion there of the paradox of analysis, and the division that Frege marks, ensuing upon his distinction of Sinn/sense from Bedeutung/reference, between two different conceptions of definition; Leibniz’s still serviceable account of a distinction between the clarity and the distinctness of ideas---a distinction that prompts the suggestion that the guiding purpose (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Incidence of Analogical Procedures in the Emergence of Mathematical Concepts. Newton and Leibniz: a Case Study.Sandra Visokolskis - 1998 - Philosophica 62 (2).
  • The Philosophy of Sophie, Electress of Hanover.Lloyd Strickland - 2009 - Hypatia 24 (2):186 - 204.
    In philosophical circles, Electress Sophie of Hanover (1630-1714) is known mainly as the friend, patron, and correspondent of Leibniz. While many scholars acknowledge Sophie's interest in philosophy, some also claim that Sophie dabbled in philosophy herself, but did not do so either seriously or competently. In this paper I show that such a view is incorrect, and that Sophie did make interesting philosophical contributions of her own, principally concerning the nature of mind and thought.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The sanskrit of science.Frits Staal - 1995 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (1):73-127.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Artificial Languages Across Sciences and Civilizations.Frits Staal - 2006 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 34 (1-2):89-141.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Leibniz and Topological Equivalence.Graham Solomon - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (4):721.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Substance and Individuation in Leibniz. [REVIEW]Alan Nelson - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (1):136-139.
    Everyone interested in Leibniz ought to read this fine, stimulating book. It is admirably written in the tradition exemplified by the references below and will especially appeal to those familiar with the analytical exposition in those works.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Nature And Necessity Of Composite Simples,e.G., Ontic Predicates.Donald Mertz - 2004 - Metaphysica 5 (1):89-133.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Leibnizian soft reduction of extrinsic denominations and relations.Ari Maunu - 2004 - Synthese 139 (1):143-164.
    Leibniz, it seems, wishes to reduce statements involving relations or extrinsic denominations to ones solely in terms of individual accidents or, respectively, intrinsic denominations. His reasons for this appear to be that relations are merely mental things (since they cannot be individual accidents) and that extrinsic denominations do not represent substances as they are on their own. Three interpretations of Leibniz''s reductionism may be distinguished: First, he allowed only monadic predicates in reducing statements (hard reductionism); second, he allowed also `implicitly (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the mind dependence of truth.Diego Marconi - 2006 - Erkenntnis 65 (3):301 - 318.
    The claim that truth is mind dependent has some initial plausibility only if truth bearers are taken to be mind dependent entities such as beliefs or statements. Even on that assumption, however, the claim is not uncontroversial. If it is spelled out as the thesis that “in a world devoid of mind nothing would be true”, then everything depends on how the phrase ‘true in world w’ is interpreted. If ‘A is true in w’ is interpreted as ‘A is true (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Leibniz's Notion of an Aggregate.Paul Lodge - 2001 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (3):467-486.
  • Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes.Martin Lin - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (1):139-143.
    The editors of this volume, in their introduction, take Jonathan Bennett’s A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics as the exemplar for the eleven essays collected here, hailing Bennett’s book as setting “new standards for philosophical research on Spinoza”. Bennett’s work is indeed a worthy model. Aside from its more generic virtues, such as learnedness and conceptual rigor, perhaps what is most distinctive about Bennett’s treatment of Spinoza is his method, which he calls the “collegial approach.” This method proceeds by studying “the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Spinoza’s Proof of Necessitarianism.Olli Koistinen - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (2):283–310.
    This paper consists of four sections. The first section considers what the proof of necessitarianism in Spinoza's system requires. Also in the first section, Jonathan Bennett's (1984) reading of 1p16 as involving a commitment to necessitarianism is presented and accepted. The second section evaluates Bennett's suggestion how Spinoza might have been led to conclude necessitarianism from his basic assumptions. The third section of the paper is devoted to Don Garrett's (1991) interpretation of Spinoza's proof. I argue that Bennett's and Garrett's (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A study of some 'separated' conditions on binary relations.I. L. Humberstone - 1991 - Theoria 57 (1-2):1-16.
  • On gödel's ontological proof.A. P. Hazen - 1998 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (3):361 – 377.
  • Leibniz on determinateness and possible worlds.Adam Harmer - 2018 - Philosophy Compass 13 (1):e12469.
    Leibniz argues that God doesn't create everything possible because not all possible things are compossible, that is, compatible with each other. Much recent debate has focused on Leibniz's conception of compossibility. One important aspect of this debate, which has not been examined directly, is the distinction between possible worlds and possible creations: the notion of possible world is more robust than simply whatever God can create. Many commentators have relied on this distinction without a clear formulation of it. I develop (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the Road from Athens to Thebes Again: Some Thirteenth-Century Thinkers on Converse Relations1.Heine Hansen - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (3):468-489.
    If Sophroniscus is the father of Socrates, then Socrates is the son of Sophroniscus. If Socrates is similar to Plato, then Plato is similar to Socrates. But how many relations does Sophroniscus and Socrates being so related involve? How many does Plato and Socrates being thus related? Is there a difference between the two cases? These are questions that have featured prominently in discussions of relations in recent years, but they are by no means new. Focusing on a text by (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neither 'Good' in Terms of 'Better' nor 'Better' in Terms of 'Good'.Johan E. Gustafsson - 2014 - Noûs 48 (1):466-473.
    In this paper, I argue against defining either of ‘good’ and ‘better’ in terms of the other. According to definitions of ‘good’ in terms of ‘better’, something is good if and only if it is better than some indifference point. Against this approach, I argue that the indifference point cannot be defined in terms of ‘better’ without ruling out some reasonable axiologies. Against defining ‘better’ in terms of ‘good’, I argue that this approach either cannot allow for the incorruptibility of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Leibniz on Body, Force and Extension.Daniel Garber & Jean-Baptiste Rauzy - 2005 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (1):347 - 368.
  • Leibnizian causation.Michael J. Futch - 2005 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (3):451-467.
    This article examines Leibniz's philosophy of causation with the aim of clarifying how causes are related to their effects. I argue that, much like J. L. Mackie's INUS conditions, Leibnizian causes are members of complex causal conditions. More precisely, Leibniz identifies causes with elements of complex causal conditions, where the complex condition as a whole is sufficient for the effect, and the cause is a necessary part of that condition. This conception of causation is able to incorporate Leibniz's many other (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leibniz's non-tensed theory of time.Michael J. Futch - 2002 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16 (2):125 – 139.
    Leibniz's philosophy of time, often seen as a precursor to current forms of relationalism and causal theories of time, has rightly earned the admiration of his more recent counterparts in the philosophy of science. In this article, I examine Leibniz's philosophy of time from a new perspective: the role that tense and non-tensed temporal properties/relations play in it. Specifically, I argue that Leibniz's philosophy of time is best (and non-anachronistically) construed as a non-tensed theory of time, one that dispenses with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sabiduría, voluntad y elección. El significado de la ‘exigencia de existencia’ y el ‘combate de los posibles’ en la metafísica de Leibniz.Agustín Echavarría - 2014 - Doispontos 11 (2).
    La finalidad de este artículo es elucidar el sentido de la doctrina leibniziana de la exigencia de existencia y el combate de los posibles, situándola dentro del conjunto de la metafísica de Leibniz y mostrando su absoluta compatibilidad con la afirmación de la creación libre y voluntaria por parte de Dios. Se intentará explicar qué elementos de la afirmación de la ‘exigencia de existencia’ y el ‘combate de los posibles’ reflejan tesis estric- tamente metafísicas, y cuáles pueden considerarse recursos metafóricos. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tautology: How not to use a word.Burton Dreben & Juliet Floyd - 1991 - Synthese 87 (1):23 - 49.
  • “Metaphysische Ergebnisse”: Phenomenology and Metaphysics in Edmund Husserl’s Cartesianische Meditationen (§60). Attempt at Commentary.Daniele De Santis - 2018 - Husserl Studies 34 (1):63-83.
    The main goal of the present paper is to offer a preliminary study of the relations between phenomenology and metaphysics in Husserl. After a brief presentation of what Husserl means by the term “metaphysics”, the rest of our research will consist of a detailed commentary on §60 of the Cartesian Meditations. Our aim is to explain in what sense, according to Husserl, the “outcomes” of the phenomenological constitution of monadological intersubjectivity entail the solution to a traditional metaphysical problem, i.e., that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thought structure, belief content, and possession conditions.Wayne A. Davis - 2008 - Acta Analytica 23 (3):207-231.
    According to Peacocke, concepts are individuated by their possession conditions, which are specified in terms of conditions in which certain propositions containing those concepts are believed. In support, Peacocke tries to explain what it is for a thought to have a structure and what it is for a belief to have a propositional content. I show that the possession condition theory cannot answer such fundamental questions. Peacocke’s theory founders because concepts are metaphysically fundamental. They individuate the propositions and thoughts containing (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Grounds and the Components of Concepts.Jan Claas - 2023 - Erkenntnis 88 (6):2409-2429.
    In this paper I investigate the idea that in conceptual analysis we are in a substantial way concerned with revealing metaphysical grounds. I argue that a recent proposal fails, according to which we aim to reveal what complex concepts are grounded in. The notion ofcomposition, rather than that ofgrounding, is the best way to understand the intuitive hierarchy of concepts. In an analysis we reveal thecomponentsorpartsof complex concepts and their structure. Finally, I propose an alternative role for grounding in our (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction: Individual Concepts in Language and Thought.Tadeusz Ciecierski & Paweł Grabarczyk - 2020 - Topoi 39 (2):349-356.
  • Modalities in language, thought and reality in Leibniz, Descartes and Crusius.Hans Burkhardt - 1988 - Synthese 75 (2):183 - 215.
  • The transzendenz of mathematical 'experience'.William Boos - 1998 - Synthese 114 (1):49-98.
  • Virtual modality. [REVIEW]William Boos - 2003 - Synthese 136 (3):435 - 491.
    Model-theoretic 1-types overa given first-order theory T may be construed as natural metalogical miniatures of G. W. Leibniz' ``complete individual notions'', ``substances'' or ``substantial forms''. This analogy prompts this essay's modal semantics for an essentiallyundecidable first-order theory T, in which one quantifies over such ``substances'' in a boolean universe V(C), where C is the completion of the Lindenbaum-algebra of T.More precisely, one can define recursively a set-theoretic translate of formulae N of formulae of a normal modal theory Tm based on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parfaits miroirs de l'univers'': A `virtual' interpretation of Leibnizian metaphysics.William Boos - 2003 - Synthese 136 (2):281 - 304.
  • Parfaits Miroirs De L'univers'': A `Virtual' Interpretation of Leibnizian Metaphysics.William Boos - 2003 - Synthese 136 (2):281-304.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Analysis of the Ontological Foundations of the Opposition of Place and Space in Modern Architecture.Flora Biabani, Mohammad Javad Safian, Shirin Toghyani & Mina Sadat Tabatabaei - 2021 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations 15 (37):418-449.
    Place is the most fundamental concept in architecture and is a necessity of architectural design, and since we face changes in our understanding of place notion in the modern era which have had distinctly profound and sometimes unpleasant effects on modern and subsequent designs- in a way that architecture has largely neglected its primary task of making the noble place of human life, and its responsibility in human dwelling dimension- in order to find the roots of the evolution in place (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cambridge and Vienna: Frank P. Ramsey and the Vienna Circle.Maria Carla Galavotti (ed.) - 2004 - Dordrecht: Springer Verlag.
    The Institute Vienna Circle held a conference in Vienna in 2003, Cambridge and Vienna a?
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant and Natural Kind Terms.Luca Forgione - 2016 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 31 (1):55-72.
    As is well known, the linguistic/philosophical reflection on natural kind terms has undergone a remarkable development in the early seventies with Putnam and Kripke’s essentialist approaches, touching upon different aspects of Kan’s slant. Preliminarily, however, it might be useful to review some of the theoretical stages in Locke and Leibniz’s approaches on natural kind terms in the light of contemporary reflections, to eventually pinpoint Kant’s contribution and see how some commentators have placed it within the theory of direct reference. Starting (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Worldlessness, Determinism and Free Will.Ari Maunu - 1999 - Dissertation, University of Turku (Finland)
    I have three main objectives in this essay. First, in chapter 2, I shall put forward and justify what I call worldlessness, by which I mean the following: All truths (as well as falsehoods) are wholly independent of any circumstances, not only time and place but also possible worlds. It follows from this view that whatever is actually true must be taken as true with respect to every possible world, which means that all truths are (in a sense) necessary. However, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bertrand Russell.Hannes Petermair - unknown
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rosenberg, reducibility and consciousness.William E. Seager - 2006 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 12.
    Rosenberg’s general argumentative strategy in favour of panpsychism is an extension of a traditional pattern. Although his argument is complex and intricate, I think a model that is historically significant and fundamentally similar to the position Rosenberg advances might help us understand the case for panpsychism. Thus I want to begin by considering a Leibnizian argument for panpsychism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Supervenience among classes of relations.S. Leuenberger - 2013 - In M. Holtje, B. Schnieder & A. Steinberg (eds.), Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence. pp. 325-346.
    This paper extends the definition of strong supervenience to cover classes of relations of any adicity, including transworld relations. It motivates that project by showing that not all interesting supervenience claims involving relations are global supervenience claims. The proposed definition has five welcome features: it reduces to the familiar definition in the special case where the classes contain only monadic properties; it equips supervenience with the expected formal properties, such as transitivity and monotonicity; it entails that a relation supervenes on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leibniz's theory of proof.Mark Julian Cass - 2013 - Scientiae Studia 11 (2):267-279.
    Leibniz propôs que demonstrações fossem reformuladas como deduções a partir de identidades, e que proposições do tipo A = A fossem a fonte única de verdade. Neste artigo, procuro explicar essa teoria da prova (e do conhecimento), assim como seus conceitos elementares, ou seja, os conceitos de identidade, verdade (ou possibilidade) e proposição (inclusive a teoria leibniziana da redutibilidade a proposições sujeito-predicado). Leibniz proposed that demonstrations be reformulated as deductions from identities, and that propositions of the type A = A (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Vague Objects and Existence.P. X. Monaghan - 2004 - Metaphysica 5 (1):59-66.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation