Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Wittgenstein and Stage-Setting: Being Brought into the Space of Reasons.David Simpson - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (6):1-16.
    Wittgenstein constantly invokes teaching, training and learning in his later work. It is therefore interesting to consider what role these notions play for him there. I argue that their use is central to Wittgenstein’s attempt to refute cognitivist assumptions, and to show how normative practices can be understood without the threat of circularity, grounded not in a kind of seeing, but in doing, and the natural reactions of an organism. This can generate a worry that Wittgenstein’s position is quietist and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and Stage-Setting: Being brought into the space of reasons.David Simpson - 2014 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 46 (6):624-639.
    I hope to clarify and explicate an account of how a creature comes to be brought into the space of reasons – that is, comes to take its place as a rational agent in social practices. My ultimate interest, however, is with a tension apparently generated by the emphasis on training coupled with this attack on cognitivism. If one’s coming to maturity depends on one being embedded in a practice, so that one comes to adopt, with ‘comfortable certainty’, the common (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Training, Training, Training.Michael Luntley - 2012 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 4 (2):88-104.
    Both Wittgenstein and Dewey have a role for the concept of skills and techniques in their understanding of practices and thereby the possession of concepts. Skills are typically acquired through training. It can seem, however, that their respective appeals to practice are dissimilar: Dewey’s appeal is, like Peirce’s, programmatic. It is meant to do philosophical work. In contrast, for Wittgenstein, the appeal to practice can seem a primitive, something that is meant to put an end to philosophical work. I argue (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Education and Initiation.Michael Luntley - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):41-56.
    In this paper I take up Peters' invitation to think of education in terms of initiation. I argue that the concept of initiation demands much closer scrutiny and analysis in order to provide a substantive thesis about education. A key challenge concerns how we conceive of the initiate. The very idea of initiation suggests that, in some interesting sense, the pupil qua initiate joins in learning activities; their role is more than that of passive recipient of values and belief. But (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Human Life, Rationality and Education.Andrea Kern - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (2):268-289.
    In this paper I explore the prospects of a Neo-Aristotelian position—according to which the difference between the human species and non-human animals is a difference in ‘form’—in the context of the question of how the human form of life is related to the idea of education. Two interpretations of this idea have been suggested by contemporary Neo-Aristotelian philosophy that offer contrasting accounts of the role played by education. According to the first, the idea of a formal difference goes with a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Critical Thinking as a Normative Practice in Life: A Wittgensteinian Groundwork.Kenny Siu Sing Huen - 2011 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 43 (10):1065-1087.
    On the point that, in practices of critical thinking, we respond spontaneously in concrete situations, this paper presents an account on behalf of Wittgenstein. I argue that the ‘seeing-things-aright’ model of Luntley's Wittgenstein is not adequate, since it pays insufficient attention to radically new circumstances, in which the content of norms is updated. While endorsing Bailin's emphasis on criteria of critical thinking, Wittgenstein would agree with Papastephanou and Angeli's demand to look behind criteriology. He maintains the primacy of the practical, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Augustine, Wittgenstein, and “the Call” in Mollenhauer’s Forgotten Connections: On Culture and Upbringing.Norm Friesen & Merilee Hamelock - 2013 - Phenomenology and Practice 6 (2):94-107.
    Augustine’s autobiographical Confessions contains one of the first accounts of a child learning to speak. This account, in turn, is central to Klaus Mollenhauer’s Forgotten Connections: On Culture and Upbringing, a book internationally regarded as one of the most important German contributions to philosophy of education and curriculum theory in the 20th century. This book’s interpretation of Augustine’s description, as well as its divergence from an earlier interpretation by Wittgenstein in his Philosophical Investigations form the initial focus of this paper, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowing and learning: from Hirst to Ofsted.Andrew John Davis - 2023 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 57 (1):214-226.
    Hirst always highlighted knowledge when reflecting on the school curriculum. He replaced his early focus on liberal education, the development of mind and theoretical knowledge by emphasizing the practical and practices as a curriculum starting point and for the framing of educational aims. In this paper I explore links between Hirst’s philosophical treatment of knowledge and some currently contested aspects of UK government education policies. I also note some ways in which his work relates to selected present-day debates in philosophy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark