Switch to: References

Citations of:

Position and change: a study in law and logic

Boston: D. Reidel Pub. Co. (1977)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Individual Rights and Legal Validity.Martin van Hees - 1996 - Analyse & Kritik 18 (1):81-95.
    The condition of liberty which Sen used in his famous theorem on the impossibility of the Paretian liberal was defined in terms of individual preferences. The preference-based approach has been the subject of much criticism, which led to the evolution of the game-theoretic analysis of rights. In this approach no references to individual preferences are made. Two questions are examined in this paper: how can different types of right be distinguished within a game-theoretic setting, and how do rights come into (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction to: Norms, Logics and Information Systems: New Studies on Deontic Logic and Computer Science.Paul McNamara & Henry Prakken - 1999 - In Henry Prakken & Paul McNamara (eds.), Norms, Logics and Information Systems: New Studies on Deontic Logic and Computer Science. Amsterdam/Oxford/Tokyo/Washington DC: IOS Press. pp. 1-14.
    (See also the separate entry for the volume itself.) This introduction has three parts. The first providing an overview of some main lines of research in deontic logic: the emergence of SDL, Chisholm's paradox and the development of dyadic deontic logics, various other puzzles/challenges and areas of development, along with philosophical applications. The second part focus on some actual and potential fruitful interactions between deontic logic, computer science and artificial intelligence. These include applications of deontic logic to AI knowledge representation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Dynamics of Thought.Peter Gardenfors - 2005 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This volume is a collection of some of the most important philosophical papers by Peter Gärdenfors. Spanning a period of more than 20 years of his research, they cover a wide ground of topics, from early works on decision theory, belief revision and nonmonotonic logic to more recent work on conceptual spaces, inductive reasoning, semantics and the evolutions of thinking. Many of the papers have only been published in places that are difficult to access. The common theme of all the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Enciclopédia de Termos Lógico-Filosóficos.João Miguel Biscaia Branquinho, Desidério Murcho & Nelson Gonçalves Gomes (eds.) - 2006 - São Paulo, SP, Brasil: Martins Fontes.
    Esta enciclopédia abrange, de uma forma introdutória mas desejavelmente rigorosa, uma diversidade de conceitos, temas, problemas, argumentos e teorias localizados numa área relativamente recente de estudos, os quais tem sido habitual qualificar como «estudos lógico-filosóficos». De uma forma apropriadamente genérica, e apesar de o território teórico abrangido ser extenso e de contornos por vezes difusos, podemos dizer que na área se investiga um conjunto de questões fundamentais acerca da natureza da linguagem, da mente, da cognição e do raciocínio humanos, bem (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Rights, goals, and capabilities.Martin van Hees - 2013 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 12 (3):247-259.
    This article analyses the relationship between rights and capabilities in order to get a better grasp of the kind of consequentialism that the capability theory represents. Capability rights have been defined as rights that have a capability as their object (rights to capabilities). Such a definition leaves the relationship between capabilities and rights to a great extent underspecified since nothing is said about the nature of those rights. Hence, it is not precluded that they are mere negative liberties, something that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Tracking and managing deemed abilities.Nicolas Troquard - 2019 - Synthese 198 (6):5027-5045.
    Information about the powers and abilities of acting entities is used to coordinate their actions in societies, either physical or digital. Yet, the commonsensical meaning of an acting entity being deemed able to do something is still missing from the existing specification languages for the web or for multi-agent systems. We advance a general purpose abstract logical account of evidence-based ability. A basic model can be thought of as the ongoing trace of a multi-agent system. Every state records systemic confirmations (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Norms that Confer Competence.Torben Spaak - 2003 - Ratio Juris 16 (1):89-104.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Legal Rights and Moral Rights: Old Questions and New Problems.Amartya Sen - 1996 - Ratio Juris 9 (2):153-167.
    The author examines the discipline of moral rights and in particular the need to embed them in a consequential system. He argues that the widely held opinion that independence from consequential evaluation is the right way of guaranteeing individual freedom is based on an inadequate appraisal of the role of moral rights in the social context. In this perspective he examines two specific cases: (1) elementary political and civil rights, and (2) the reproductive rights of women in the context of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Getting started: Beginnings in the logic of action.Krister Segerberg - 1992 - Studia Logica 51 (3-4):347 - 378.
    A history of the logic of action is outlined, beginning with St Anselm. Five modern authors are discussed in some detail: von Wright, Fitch, Kanger, Chellas and Pratt.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • ¿Existen dos clases de normas: regulatorias y de competencia?Ulises Schmill Ordoñez - 2013 - Análisis Filosófico 33 (2):186-210.
    El ensayo que presento intenta establecer la unidad conceptual entre las llamadas normas regulatorias y las normas de competencia. Para ello se hace una construcción conceptual de la norma jurídica y del orden jurídico, cuando existe una pluralidad de normas. Con base en ello se ofrece un esquema del orden jurídico que comprende tanto a las normas regulatorias como a las de competencia, estableciendo la unidad entre ambas clases de normas, considerando que las normas regulatorias son una parte de las (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Henning herrestad, formal theories of rights.Giovanni Sartor - 2000 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 8 (1):93-100.
  • Fundamental legal concepts: A formal and teleological characterisation. [REVIEW]Giovanni Sartor - 2006 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 14 (1-2):101-142.
    We shall introduce a set of fundamental legal concepts, providing a definition of each of them. This set will include, besides the usual deontic modalities (obligation, prohibition and permission), the following notions: obligative rights (rights related to other’s obligations), permissive rights, erga-omnes rights, normative conditionals, liability rights, different kinds of legal powers, potestative rights (rights to produce legal results), result-declarations (acts intended to produce legal determinations), and sources of the law.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Rights theory.George W. Rainbolt - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (1):11–21.
    Both moral and legal theory feature prominent talk about rights. Yet there is very little agreement about what rights are, about why we use rights in our moral or legal theories, or about what to do when there is a conflict between rights. This article surveys many of the popular theory for analysing rights and explaining their scope.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Validez, reconocimiento y potestades normativas.Claudina Orunesu & Jorge L. Rodríguez - 2013 - Análisis Filosófico 33 (2):145-169.
    ¿Cómo justificar la validez jurídica de aquellas normas cuya creación no puede ser evaluada como regular o irregular por apelación a ninguna otra norma jurídica? Entre las respuestas más ilustres a este problema se cuentan la norma fundante kelseniana y la regla de reconocimiento de Hart, pero cada una de esas ideas ha sido objeto de serias críticas. Eugenio Bulygin ha efectuado aportes decisivos en esta discusión: ha advertido que cuando se examina el fundamento último de la validez de las (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ownership: A case study in the representation of legal concepts. [REVIEW]L. Thorne McCarty - 2002 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 10 (1-3):173-190.
    This article is an exercise in computational jurisprudence. It seems clear thatthe field of AI and Law should draw upon the insights of legal philosophers,whenever possible. But can the computational perspective offer anything inreturn? I will explore this question by focusing on the concept of OWNERSHIP,which has been debated in the jurisprudential literature for centuries. Althoughthe intellectual currents here flow mostly in one direction – from legal philosophy to AI – I will show that there are also some insights to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On attributing rights to all peoples: Some logical questions. [REVIEW]David Makinson - 1989 - Law and Philosophy 8 (1):53 - 63.
  • Five faces of minimality.David Makinson - 1993 - Studia Logica 52 (3):339 - 379.
    We discuss similarities and residual differences, within the general semantic framework of minimality, between defeasible inference, belief revision, counterfactual conditionals, updating — and also conditional obligation in deontic logic. Our purpose is not to establish new results, but to bring together existing material to form a clear overall picture.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Normative-informational positions: a modal-logical approach.Andrew J. I. Jones & Xavier Parent - 2008 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 16 (1):7-23.
    This paper is a preliminary investigation into the application of the formal-logical theory of normative positions to the characterisation of normative-informational positions, pertaining to rules that are meant to regulate the supply of information. First, we present the proposed framework. Next, we identify the kinds of nuances and distinctions that can be articulated in such a logical framework. Finally, we show how such nuances can arise in specific regulations. Reference is made to Data Protection Law and Contract Law, among others. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Individuals and collective actions.Sven Ove Hansson - 1986 - Theoria 52 (1-2):87-97.
  • Donald NUTE (ed.), Defeasible deontic logic.Jaap Hage - 2000 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 8 (1):75-91.
  • A model of juridical acts: part 2: the operation of juridical acts. [REVIEW]Jaap Hage - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 19 (1):49-73.
    This paper aims at providing an account of juridical acts that forms a suitable starting point for the creation of computational systems that deal with juridical acts. The paper is divided into two parts. This second part of the paper deals in some detail with the operation of juridical acts. Topics dealt with include: power and competence, capacity, form requirements, partial validity, avoidance and representation.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A computational framework for institutional agency.Guido Governatori & Antonino Rotolo - 2008 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 16 (1):25-52.
    This paper provides a computational framework, based on defeasible logic, to capture some aspects of institutional agency. Our background is Kanger-Lindahl-Pörn account of organised interaction, which describes this interaction within a multi-modal logical setting. This work focuses in particular on the notions of counts-as link and on those of attempt and of personal and direct action to realise states of affairs. We show how standard defeasible logic (DL) can be extended to represent these concepts: the resulting system preserves some basic (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Normative autonomy and normative co-ordination: Declarative power, representation, and mandate. [REVIEW]Jonathan Gelati, Antonino Rotolo, Giovanni Sartor & Guido Governatori - 2004 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 12 (1-2):53-81.
    In this paper we provide a formal analysis of the idea of normative co-ordination. We argue that this idea is based on the assumption that agents can achieve flexible co-ordination by conferring normative positions to other agents. These positions include duties, permissions, and powers. In particular, we explain the idea of declarative power, which consists in the capacity of the power-holder of creating normative positions, involving other agents, simply by proclaiming such positions. In addition, we account also for the concepts (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Deontic Logic and Normative Systems.Olivier Roy, Allard Tamminga & Malte Willer (eds.) - 2016 - London, UK: College Publications.
    The biennial DEON conferences are designed to promote interdisciplinary cooperation amongst scholars interested in linking the formal-logical study of normative concepts and normative systems with computer science, artificial intelligence, linguistics, philosophy, organization theory and law. In addition to these general themes, DEON 2016 encouraged a special focus on the topic "Reasons, Argumentation and Justification.".
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamic Logic of Legal Competences.Huimin Dong & Olivier Roy - 2021 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (4):701-724.
    We propose a new formalization of legal competences, and in particular for the Hohfeldian categories of power and immunity, through a deontic reinterpretation of dynamic epistemic logic. We argue that this logic explicitly captures the norm-changing character of legal competences while providing a sophisticated reduction of the latter to static normative positions. The logic is completely axiomatizable, and we apply it to a concrete case in German contract law to illustrate that it can capture the distinction between legal ability and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does Legal Semiotics Cannibalize Jurisprudence?José de Sousa E. Brito - 2009 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 22 (4):387-398.
    Does Duncan Kennedy successfully cannibalize jurisprudence? He attempts to do it by demonstrating the inexistence of rightness in legal argumentation. If there is no right legal argument, then there is no right answer in adjudication, adjudication is not a rational enterprise and legal doctrine cannot be said to be a science. It can be shown that skepticism is self-defeating. Duncan Kennedy can avoid self defeat only because he actually believes in a lot of legal arguments. His thesis that judges decide (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contract automata: An operational view of contracts between interactive parties.Shaun Azzopardi, Gordon J. Pace, Fernando Schapachnik & Gerardo Schneider - 2016 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 24 (3):203-243.
    Deontic logic as a way of formally reasoning about norms, an important area in AI and law, has traditionally concerned itself about formalising provisions of general statutes. Despite the long history of deontic logic, given the wide scope of the logic, it is difficult, if not impossible, to formalise all these notions in a single formalism, and there are still ongoing debates on appropriate semantics for deontic modalities in different contexts. In this paper, we restrict our attention to contracts between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The elementary theory of collective action.Leo Apostel - 1978 - Philosophica 21:129-157.
  • Computability of diagrammatic theories for normative positions.Matteo Pascucci & Giovanni Sileno - 2021 - In Erich Schweighofer (ed.), Legal Knowledge and Information Systems. Proceedings of JURIX 2021. IOS Press. pp. 171-180.
    Normative positions are sometimes illustrated in diagrams, in particular in didactic contexts. Traditional examples are the Aristotelian polygons of opposition for deontic modalities (squares, triangles, hexagons, etc.), and the Hohfeldian squares for obligative and potestative concepts. Relying on previous work, we show that Hohfeld’s framework can be used as a basis for developing several Aristotelian polygons and more complex diagrams. Then, we illustrate how logical theories of increasing strength can be built based on these diagrams, and how those theories enable (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fundamental Legal Concepts: A Teleological Characterisation.Giovanni Sartor - forthcoming - Artificial Intelligence and Law.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deontic Logic.Paul McNamara - 2006 - In Dov Gabbay & John Woods (eds.), The Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 7: Logic and the Modalities in the Twentieth Century. Elsevier Press. pp. 197-288.
    Overview of fundamental work in deontic logic.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Norm Performatives and Deontic Logic.Rosja Mastop - 2011 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 7 (2):83-105.
    Deontic logic is standardly conceived as the logic of true statements about the existence of obligations and permissions. In his last writings on the subject, G. H. von Wright criticized this view of deontic logic, stressing the rationality of norm imposition as the proper foundation of deontic logic. The present paper is an attempt to advance such an account of deontic logic using the formal apparatus of update semantics and dynamic logic. That is, we first define norm systems and a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hohfeld relations and spielraum for action.Lars Lindahl - 2006 - Análisis Filosófico 26 (2):325-355.
    The paper intends to show, that W. N. Hohfeld's theory of fundamental jural relations is relevant to economic theory, and that Hohfeld's system can be reconstructed by the concepts of 'liberty space' and 'ability space', understood as an agent's Spielraum for action. The first half of the paper is devoted to an exposition of Hohfeld's system and to the question of its relation to the economic analysis of property rights. The second half concerns Spielraum theory and the reformulation of Hohfeldian (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The search for symmetry in Hohfeldian modalities.Matteo Pascucci & Giovanni Sileno - 2021 - In Amrita Basu, Gem Stapleton, Sven Linker, Catherine Legg, Emmanuel Manalo & Petrucio Viana (eds.), Diagrammatic Representation and Inference. Proceedings of Diagrams 2021. Springer. pp. 87-102.
    In this work we provide an analysis of some issues arising with geometrical representations of a family of deontic and potestative relations that can be classified as Hohfeldian modalities, traditionally illustrated on two diagrams, the Hohfeldian squares. Our main target is the lack of symmetry to be found in various formal accounts by drawing analogies with the square of opposition for alethic modalities. We argue that one should rather rely on an analogy with the alethic hexagon of opposition and exploit (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Commanding and Defining. On Eugenio Bulygin’s Theory of Legal Power-Conferring Rules.Gonzalo Villa Rosas - 2017 - Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 49 (146):75-105.
    This paper aims to explore two objections raised against Bulygin’s second approach to the definition of the nature of legal power-conferring rules. According to the first objection, such an account is vague about what is defined by legal power-conferring rules qua constitutive rules. I maintain that this vagueness is rooted in the lack of a suitable definition of legal power. I shall be arguing for the reduction of the complexity of the definientia by defining legal power as a species of (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark