Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Killing for knowledge.Tzachi Zamir - 2006 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (1):17–40.
    abstract I distinguish between four arguments commonly used to justify experimentation on animals (I). After delineating the autonomy of the question of experiments from other topics within animal ethics (II), I examine and reject each of these justifications (III–VI). I then explore two arguments according to which animal‐dependent experimentation should continue even if it is immoral (VII). I close with the way in which liberationists’ strategic considerations modify the moral conclusions of my analysis.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Consumer demand theory and animal welfare: Value and limitations.Tina Widowski - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):45-45.
  • Precision Livestock Farming and Farmers’ Duties to Livestock.Ian Werkheiser - 2018 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 31 (2):181-195.
    Precision livestock farming promises to allow modern, large-scale farms to replicate, at scale, caring farmers who know their animals. PLF refers to a suite of technologies, some only speculative. The goal is to use networked devices to continuously monitor individual animals on large farms, to compare this information to expected norms, and to use algorithms to manage individual animals automatically. Supporters say this could not only create an artificial version of the partially mythologized image of the good steward caring for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • “Perceived cost” may reveal frustration, but not boredom.Françoise Wemelsfelder - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):44-44.
  • Who suffers?P. D. Wall - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):43-44.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Natural and unnatural justice in animal care.Stephen Walker - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):43-43.
  • Paradoxical experimental outcomes and animal suffering.Jaylan Sheila Turkkan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):42-43.
  • Pain, suffering, and distress.Aubrey Townsend - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):41-42.
  • Broadening the welfare index.Frederick Toates - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):40-41.
  • The attribution of suffering.William Timberlake - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):38-40.
  • Species as a relationship.Julia Tanner - 2008 - Acta Analytica 23 (4):337-347.
    The fact that humans have a special relationship to each other insofar as they belong in the same species is often taken to be a morally relevant difference between humans and other animals, one which justifies a greater moral status for all humans, regardless of their individual capacities. I give some reasons why this kind of relationship is not an appropriate ground for differential treatment of humans and nonhumans. I then argue that even if relationships do matter morally species membership (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Clarifying the Concept of Cruelty: What Makes Cruelty to Animals Cruel.Julia Tanner - 2015 - Heythrop Journal 56 (5):818-835.
    The topic of cruelty features regularly in discussions concerning animals’ moral status. Further, condemnation of cruelty to animals is virtually unanimous. As Regan points out, ‘[i]t would be difficult to find anyone who is in favour of cruelty.’ What is to count as cruelty is therefore important. My aim here is to gain a clearer understanding of one aspect of our moral landscape: cruelty to animals. I will start by analyzing the concept of cruelty in section II. In section III (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Can the treatment of animals be compared to the holocaust?David Sztybel - 2006 - Ethics and the Environment 11 (1):97-132.
    : The treatment of animals and the Holocaust have been compared many times before, but never has a thoroughly detailed comparison been offered. A thirty-nine-point comparison can be constructed, whether or not one believes that animals are oppressed. The question of whether or not the comparison ought to be expressed merely brings into question whether animal liberationists have liberal-democratic rights to express themselves, which they surely do. Four objections are considered: Is the comparison offensive? Does the comparison trivialize what happened (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Can the Treatment of Animals Be Compared to the Holocaust?David Sztybel - 2006 - Ethics and the Environment 11 (1):97-132.
    The treatment of animals and the Holocaust have been compared many times before, but never has a thoroughly detailed comparison been offered. A thirty-nine-point comparison can be constructed, whether or not one believes that animals are oppressed. The question of whether or not the comparison ought to be expressed merely brings into question whether animal liberationists have liberal-democratic rights to express themselves, which they surely do. Four objections are considered: Is the comparison offensive? Does the comparison trivialize what happened to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Animal confinement and use.Robert Streiffer & David Killoren - 2019 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):1-21.
    We distinguish two conceptions of confinement – the agential conception and the comparative conception – and show that the former is intimately related to use in a way that the latter is not. Specifically, in certain conditions, agential confinement constitutes use and creates a special relationship that makes neglect or abuse especially egregious. This allows us to develop and defend an account of one important way in which agential confinement can be morally wrong. We then discuss some of the account’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Forethoughts for Carnivores.Stewart Richards - 1981 - Philosophy 56 (215):73 - 87.
    Philosophers have taken some salutary exercise in recent years—notably in this journal—on the question of the rights of non-human animals and the obligations of human to non-human individuals and species. In so contentious an area there has been striking unanimity on two aspects. One of these is that, irrespective of the merits of the arguments on specific issues, this is a matter which is bound to affect the conduct of our lives. The other is that, other things being equal, it (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Your Daughter or Your Dog? A Feminist Assessment of the Animal Research Issue.Deborah Slicer - 1991 - Hypatia 6 (1):108-124.
    I bring several ecofeminist critiques of deep ecology to bear on mainstream animal rights theories, especially on the rights and utilitarian treatments of the animal research issue. Throughout, I show how animal rights issues are feminist issues and clarify the relationship between ecofeminism and animal rights.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The significance of animal suffering.Peter Singer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):9-12.
  • Ethics and animals.Peter Singer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):45-48.
  • Thinking about the good: Reconfiguring liberal metaphysics (or not) for people with cognitive disabilities.Anita Silvers & Leslie Pickering Francis - 2009 - Metaphilosophy 40 (3-4):475-498.
    Liberalism welcomes diversity in substantive ideas of the good but not in the process whereby these ideas are formed. Ideas of the good acquire weight on the presumption that each is a person's own, formed independently. But people differ in their capacities to conceptualize. Some, appropriately characterized as cerebral, are proficient in and profoundly involved with conceptualizing. Others, labeled cognitively disabled, range from individuals with mild limitations to those so unable to express themselves that we cannot be sure whether their (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • From one subjectivity to another.S. J. Shettleworth & N. Mrosovsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):37-38.
  • Animal well-being: There are many paths to enlightenment.Evalyn F. Segal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):36-37.
  • The meaning of speciesism and the forms of animal suffering.S. F. Sapontzis - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):35-36.
  • Emotion, empathy, and suffering.Eric A. Salzen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):34-35.
  • To suffer, or not to suffer? That is the question.Andrew N. Rowan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):33-34.
  • Science and value.Bernard E. Rollin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):32-33.
  • Suffering as a behaviourist views it.Howard Rachlin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):32-32.
  • Transferring Morality to Human–Nonhuman Chimeras.Monika Piotrowska - 2014 - American Journal of Bioethics 14 (2):4-12.
    Human–nonhuman chimeras have been the focus of ethical controversies for more than a decade, yet some related issues remain unaddressed. For example, little has been said about the relationship between the origin of transferred cells and the morally relevant capacities to which they may give rise. Consider, for example, a developing mouse fetus that receives a brain stem cell transplant from a human and another that receives a brain stem cell transplant from a dolphin. If both chimeras acquire morally relevant (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Seeking the sources of simian suffering.Melinda A. Novak & Jerrold S. Meyer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):31-32.
  • The case for and difficulties in using “demand areas” to measure changes in well-being.Yew-Kwang Ng - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):30-31.
  • Children and the Argument from 'Marginal' Cases.Amy Mullin - 2011 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 14 (3):291-305.
    I characterize the main approaches to the moral consideration of children developed in the light of the argument from 'marginal' cases, and develop a more adequate strategy that provides guidance about the moral responsibilities adults have towards children. The first approach discounts the significance of children's potential and makes obligations to all children indirect, dependent upon interests others may have in children being treated well. The next approaches agree that the potential of children is morally considerable, but disagree as to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Consumer demand: Can we deal with differing priorities?P. Monaghan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):29-30.
  • Welcoming, Wild Animals, and Obligations to Assist.Josh Milburn - 2021 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 34 (6):1-20.
    What we could call ‘relational non-interventionism’ holds that we have no general obligation to alleviate animal suffering, and that we do not typically have special obligations to alleviate wild animals’ suffering. Therefore, we do not usually have a duty to intervene in nature to alleviate wild animal suffering. However, there are a range of relationships that we may have with wild animals that do generate special obligations to aid—and the consequences of these obligations can be surprising. In this paper, it (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Welcoming, Wild Animals, and Obligations to Assist.Josh Milburn - 2023 - Ethics, Policy and Environment 26 (2):231-248.
    What we could call ‘relational non-interventionism’ holds that we have no general obligation to alleviate animal suffering, and that we do not typically have special obligations to alleviate wild animals’ suffering. Therefore, we do not generally have a duty to intervene in nature to alleviate wild animal suffering. However, there are a range of relationships that we may have with wild animals that do generate special obligations to aid – and the consequences of these obligations can be surprising. In this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Development experience and the potential for suffering: Does “out of experience” mean “out of mind”?Michael Mendl - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):28-29.
  • Consumer demand theory and social behavior: All chickens are not equal.Joy A. Mench & W. Ray Stricklin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):28-28.
  • Suffering by analogy.David McFarland - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):27-27.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Obtaining and applying objective criteria in animal welfare.Anne E. Magurran - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):26-27.
  • Hidden adaptationism.David Magnus & Peter Thiel - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):26-26.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Science and subjective feelings.Dale Jamieson - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):25-26.
  • Singer's intermediate conclusion.Frank Jackson - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):24-25.
  • Experimental investigation of animal suffering.B. O. Hughes & J. C. Petherick - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):23-24.
  • Reasonable Partiality to Domestic Animals.Robert Heeger - 2005 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (1-2):123-139.
    The paper deals with partiality flowing from special relationships. Two main problems are discussed. The first concerns the relationship between partiality and genuine moral obligations. If partiality can bring about such obligations only if it is reasonable, what requirements should it meet in order to be reasonable? The second problem is one of animal ethics. Can the concept of reasonable partiality help us articulate what is morally at stake in a current discussion about the treatment of domestic animals, viz. the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Animals, Relations, and the Laissez-Faire Intuition.Trevor Hedberg - 2016 - Environmental Values 25 (4):427-442.
    In Animal Ethics in Context, Clare Palmer tries to harmonise two competing approaches to animal ethics. One focuses on the morally relevant capacities that animals possess. The other is the Laissez-Faire Intuition (LFI): the claim that we have duties to assist domesticated animals but should (at least generally) leave wild animals alone. In this paper, I critique the arguments that Palmer offers in favour of the No-Contact LFI - the view that we have (prima facie) duties not to harm wild (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reframing the Ethical Issues in Part-Human Animal Research: The Unbearable Ontology of Inexorable Moral Confusion.Matthew H. Haber & Bryan Benham - 2012 - American Journal of Bioethics 12 (9):17-25.
    Research that involves the creation of animals with human-derived parts opens the door to potentially valuable scientific and therapeutic advances, yet invokes unsettling moral questions. Critics and champions alike stand to gain from clear identification and careful consideration of the strongest ethical objections to this research. A prevailing objection argues that crossing the human/nonhuman species boundary introduces inexorable moral confusion (IMC) that warrants a restriction to this research on precautionary grounds. Though this objection may capture the intuitions of many who (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • In defence of speciesism.J. A. Gray - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):22-23.
  • Animals, science, and morality.R. G. Frey - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):22-22.
  • Concepts of suffering in veterinary science.Andrew F. Fraser - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):21-22.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Taking the animal's viewpoint seriously.Michael Allen Fox - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):20-21.
  • The philosophical foundations of animal welfare.John Dupré - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):19-20.