Switch to: References

Citations of:

The monadology and other philosophical writings

New York: Garland. Edited by Robert Latta (1898)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Belief, Credence, and Pragmatic Encroachment.Jacob Ross & Mark Schroeder - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (2):259-288.
    This paper compares two alternative explanations of pragmatic encroachment on knowledge (i.e., the claim that whether an agent knows that p can depend on pragmatic factors). After reviewing the evidence for such pragmatic encroachment, we ask how it is best explained, assuming it obtains. Several authors have recently argued that the best explanation is provided by a particular account of belief, which we call pragmatic credal reductivism. On this view, what it is for an agent to believe a proposition is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   207 citations  
  • Leibniz, Whitehead, and the metaphysics of causation.Pierfrancesco Basile - 2009 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    This book introduces the reader to Whitehead’s complex and often misunderstood metaphysics by showing that it deals with questions about the nature of causation originally raised by the philosophy of Leibniz. Whitehead’s philosophy is an attempt at rehabilitating Leibniz’s theory of monads by recasting it in terms of novel ontological categories.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • It Must be True – But How Can it Be? Some Remarks on Panpsychism and Mental Composition.Pierfrancesco Basile - 2010 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 67:93-112.
    Although panpsychism has had a very long history, one that goes back to the very origin of western philosophy, its force has only recently been appreciated by analytic philosophers of mind. And even if many still reject the theory as utterly absurd, others have argued that it is the only genuine form of physicalism. This paper examines the case for panpsychism and argues that there are at least goodprima faciereasons for taking it seriously. In a second step, the paper discusses (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Essential Difference: Toward a Metaphysics of Emergence.James Blachowicz - 2012 - State University of New York Press.
    Proposes a new way of understanding the nature of metaphysics, focusing on nonreductionist emergence theory, both in ancient and modern philosophy, as well as in contemporary philosophy of science.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Consciousness, Machines, and Moral Status.Henry Shevlin - manuscript
    In light of recent breakneck pace in machine learning, questions about whether near-future artificial systems might be conscious and possess moral status are increasingly pressing. This paper argues that as matters stand these debates lack any clear criteria for resolution via the science of consciousness. Instead, insofar as they are settled at all, it is likely to be via shifts in public attitudes brought about by the increasingly close relationships between humans and AI users. Section 1 of the paper I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In support of cognitive theories.Thomas R. Zentall - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):654.
  • Is “Behaviorism at fifty” twenty years older?Everett J. Wyers - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):653.
  • Operant conditioning and behavioral neuroscience.Michael L. Woodruff - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):652.
  • Could God create Darwinian accidents?John S. Wilkins - 2012 - Zygon 47 (1):30-42.
    Abstract Charles Darwin, in his discussions with Asa Gray and in his published works, doubted whether God could so arrange it that exactly the desired contingent events would occur to cause particular outcomes by natural selection. In this paper, I argue that even a limited or neo-Leibnizian deity could have chosen a world that satisfied some arbitrary set of goals or functions in its outcomes and thus answer Darwin's conundrum. In more general terms, this supports the consistency of natural selection (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The development of concepts of the mental world.Henry M. Wellman - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):651.
  • Hamilton, Hamiltonian Mechanics, and Causation.Christopher Gregory Weaver - 2023 - Foundations of Science:1-45.
    I show how Sir William Rowan Hamilton’s philosophical commitments led him to a causal interpretation of classical mechanics. I argue that Hamilton’s metaphysics of causation was injected into his dynamics by way of a causal interpretation of force. I then detail how forces are indispensable to both Hamilton’s formulation of classical mechanics and what we now call Hamiltonian mechanics (i.e., the modern formulation). On this point, my efforts primarily consist of showing that the contemporary orthodox interpretation of potential energy is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Models, yes; homunculus, no.Frederick M. Toates - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):650.
  • Are radical and cognitive behaviorism incompatible?Roger K. Thomas - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):650.
  • “Mental way stations” in contemporary theories of animal learning.William S. Terry - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):649.
  • Reproduction versus metamorphosis: Hegel and the evolutionary thinking of his time.Márcio Suzuki - 2020 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 42 (3):1-22.
    Several problems with Hegel’s conception of the organism in the Encyclopaedia are due to the separation between individual life in Nature and the universal life of the Concept. This discontinuity between ontogenesis and phylogenesis in his dialectics of organic life will be studied here by following his presentation of physiological development, especially reproduction, and by reconstructing the historical model he criticizes—Leibniz’s organic machines and their development in Buffon’s Natural History—a model that was also of crucial importance to the philosophy of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Infinity, infinite processes and limit concepts: recovering a neglected background of social and critical theory.Piet Strydom - 2017 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 43 (8):793-811.
    This article seeks to recover a neglected chapter in the historical and theoretical background of social theory in general and critical theory in particular with a view to refining the understanding of the presuppositions of a cognitively enhanced critical social science appropriate to our troubled times. For this purpose, it offers a brief reconstruction of the mathematical-philosophical tradition from ancient to modern times by extrapolating that part of it that is marked by the ideas of infinity, infinite processes and limit (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is behaviorism vacuous?Stephen P. Stich - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):647.
  • Skinner's behaviorism implies a subcutaneous homunculus.J. E. R. Staddon - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):647.
  • Representations and misrepresentations.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):655.
  • Behaviorism at fifty.B. F. Skinner - 1974 - New York,: J. Norton Publishers.
    Each of us is uniquely subject to certain kinds of stimulation from a small part of the universe within our skins. Mentalistic psychologies insist that other kinds of events, lacking the physical dimensions of stimuli, are accessible to the owner of the skin within which they occur. One solution often regarded as behavioristic, granting the distinction between public and private events and ruling the latter out of consideration, has not been successful. A science of behavior must face the problem of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Explaining behavior Skinner's way.Michael A. Simon - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):646.
  • Cognitive science at seven: A wolf at the door for behaviorism?Miriam W. Schustack & Jaime G. Carbonell - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):645.
  • Categorial Differences: Plessner’s Philosophy Far from Reductive Naturalism and from Idealistic Culturalism.Volker Schürmann - 2019 - Human Studies 42 (1):31-45.
    Plessner’s philosophical anthropology is presented as a non-naturalistic philosophy of nature. Such a position is attractive and indispensable, for instance, to all debates concerning personhood and human dignity. Plessner’s work rests on a conception of philosophy that distinguishes without exception the contents of possible experiences from their conditions of possibility. Thus, Plessner’s anthropology is a theory of categorial contents, but not in the aprioric sense according to which they would be assumed to be prior to all experience. Plessner avoids such (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Behaviorism at fifty” at twenty.Roger Schnaitter - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):644.
  • Michaux: Xenopathic Ontology.Arun Saldanha - 2012 - Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 6 (3):411-437.
    The hallucinogenic art of Michaux and other surrealists should never be regarded as advocating unbridled sensuous experimentation. The affects they generate may index absurdity, incongruity and comedy – they may ‘ridiculise’ our systematic thinking – but these affects thereby serve a more serious production of concepts. Through an abstemious aesthetics of existence Michaux becomes an ontologist of the prephilosophical sort. Carefully but ambiguously he explores the truths of matter, movement, body and modernity. As Deleuze saw clearly, the resulting ontology has (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The behaviorist concept of mind.David M. Rosenthal - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):643.
  • Behaviorism at Seventy.Daniel N. Robinson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):641-643.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ontology and ideology of behaviorism and mentalism.Georges Rey - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):640.
  • Belief-level way stations.Donald Perlis - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):639.
  • Introspection as the key to mental life.Chris Mortensen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):639.
  • A cognitivist reply to behaviorism.Robert C. Moore - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):637.
  • What does the conservation of energy have to do with physicalism?Barbara Montero - 2006 - Dialectica 60 (4):383-396.
    The conservation of energy law, a law of physics that states that the total energy of any closed system is always conserved, is a bedrock principle that has achieved both broad theoretical and experimental support. Yet if interactive dualism is correct, it is thought that the mind can affect physical objects in violation of the conservation of energy. Thus, some claim, the conservation of energy grounds an argument for physicalism. Although critics of the argument focus on the implausibility of causation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Deriving Actuality from Possibility.Mohsen Moghri - 2020 - Philosophia 49 (1):393-402.
    Many believe that the world exists without a cause or reason. Most of them reject an explanation for the whole concrete world because they accept the traditional idea that concrete existence comes only from things that concretely exist. But I provide reasons for thinking that the world might be actual as a result of a feature that is not concrete but abstract. I begin by outlining ideas that some followers of the Platonic Theory of Forms have developed about whether actuality (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy and the future of behaviorism.M. Jackson Marr - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):636.
  • Mechanism at two thousand.John C. Marshall - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):637.
  • Behaviorism and “the problem of privacy”.William Lyons - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):635.
  • Skinner and the mind–body problem.William G. Lycan - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):634.
  • Artificially intelligent mental models.Michael Lebowitz - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):633.
  • The Impossible project of Ivan Pavlov.David Joravsky - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (2):265-280.
    The ArgumentIn different contexts, beginning with different concerns, Pavlov, James, and Freud tried to achieve a neurophysiological explanation of mind, and suffered defeat. James and Freud acknowledged the defeat and attempted, in radically different ways, to construct an interim psychology, hoping that neural explanation would be achieved in the future. Pavlov came to the effort in his fifties, after decades of research that took for granted a sharp separation between neurophysiology and psychology. He changed his mind as he noticed the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What's on the minds of children?Carl N. Johnson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):632.
  • J. B. Watson's imagery and other mentalistic problems.Francis W. Irwin - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):632.
  • B. F. Skinner's confused philosophy of science.Laurence Hitterdale - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):630.
  • Affordances and Landscapes: Overcoming the Nature–Culture Dichotomy through Niche Construction Theory.Manuel Heras-Escribano & Manuel De Pinedo-García - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
  • I've got you under my skin.John Heil - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):629.
  • Leibnizian privacy and Skinnerian privacy.Keith Gunderson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):628.
  • What did Russell learn from Leibniz?Nicholas Griffin - 2013 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 2 (1).
    Russell’s rejection in 1898 of the doctrine of internal relations — the view that all relations are grounded in the intrinsic properties of the terms related — was a decisive part of his break with Hegelianism and opened the way for his turn to analytic philosophy. Before rejecting it, Russell had given the doctrine little thought, though it played an essential role in the most intractable of the problems facing his attempt to construct a Hegelian dialectic of the sciences. I (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A causal role for “conscious” seeing.Robert M. Gordon - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):628.
  • In search of a theory of learning.Alison Gopnik - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):627.
  • Consciousness, explanation, and the verbal community.Gordon G. Gallup - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):626.
  • Undifferentiated and “mote-beam” percepts in Watsonian-Skinnerian behaviorism.John J. Furedy & Diane M. Riley - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):625.