Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Sustancia, sucesión y permanencia según Aristóteles.Alejandro G. Vigo - 1998 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 14 (1):153-191.
    Este artículo subraya la incidencia de un componente temporal en la doctrina aristotélica de la sustancia y las categorías en la medida en que la distinción sustancia-accidentes se refiere no sólo a la oposición lógica entre el sujeto y el predicado, sino también a la oposición real entre el sujeto de cambio y sus determinaciones. El argumento se basa en la interpretación de importantes pasajes de Cat. 5, Phys. I, 7 y IV 10-14.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Synchronic Justification for Aristotle's Commitment to Prime Matter.Margaret Scharle - 2009 - Phronesis 54 (4-5):326-345.
    The current debate over Aristotle's commitment to prime matter is centered on diachronic considerations found in his theory of substantial change. I argue that an appeal to this theory is not required in order to establish his commitment to the existence of prime matter. By drawing on Physics II.1's conception of what it is for an element to have a nature - that is, to have an inner source of movement and rest - I introduce a synchronic justification for the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Keturių elementų metafiziškumas Aristotelio fizikoje.Jonas Čiurlionis - 2017 - Problemos 91:115.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Metaphysical Distinction Between Processes and Events.Kathleen Gill - 1993 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (3):365-384.
    In theMetaphysics, Aristotle pointed out that some activities are engaged in for their own sake, while others are directed at some end. The test for distinguishing between them is to ask, ‘At any time during a period in which someone is Xing, is it also true that they have Xed?’ If both are true, the activity is being done for its own sake. If not, it is being done for the sake of some end other than itself. For example, if (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • De Generatione et Corruptione 2.3: Does Aristotle Identify The Contraries As Elements?Timothy J. Crowley - 2013 - Classical Quarterly 63 (1):161-182.
    It might seem quite commonplace to say that Aristotle identifies fire, air, water and earth as the στοιχεῖα, or ‘elements’ – or, to be more precise, as the elements of bodies that are subject to generation and corruption. Yet there is a tradition of interpretation, already evident in the work of the sixth-century commentator John Philoponus and widespread, indeed prevalent, today, according to which Aristotle does not really believe that fire, air, water and earth are truly elemental. The basic premise (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle's 'So-Called Elements'.Timothy Crowley - 2008 - Phronesis 53 (3):223-242.
    Aristotle's use of the phrase τὰ καλούμενα στοιχεȋα is usually taken as evidence that he does not really think that the things to which this phrase refers, namely, fire, air, water, and earth, are genuine elements. In this paper I question the linguistic and textual grounds for taking the phrase τὰ καλούμενα στοιχεȋα in this way. I offer a detailed examination of the significance of the phrase, and in particular I compare Aristotle's general use of the Greek participle καλούμενος (-η, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Prime Matter: a Rejoinder.William Charlton - 1983 - Phronesis 28 (2):197-211.