Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Heroes and Demigods: Aristotle's Hypothetical "Defense" of True Nobles.William H. Harwood & Paria Akhgari - 2023 - Eirene 59 (I-II):67-98.
    Although the commentary on Aristotle’s problematic discussion of slavery is vast, his discussion of nobility receives little attention. The fragments of his dialogue On Noble Birth constitute his most extensive examination of nobility, and while their similarity to the παμβασιλεύς of the Politics has recently been recognized, their relevance to natural slavery has hitherto gone unnoticed. Yet by declaring that true nobles – particularly the god-like ἀρχηγός – preternaturally possess superhuman characteristics, Aristotle precludes their easy inclusion in the kind “human” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ciceronov de fato: o helenističkim kondicionalima i slobodi volje.Vladimir Marko - 2023 - Novi Sad: Futura publikacije.
    Cicero's De fato: On Hellenistic Conditionals and Free Will. The Serbo-Croatian translation of Cicero's De fato, with comments and detailed analysis of some arguments and problems of the text. -/- (s/h): Tekst Ciceronovog spisa "de fato", prevod, komentari i u dodacima, detaljnija analiza pojedinih argumenata i problema sadržanih u tekstu.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Definition and essence in Metaphysics vii 4.Lucas Angioni - 2014 - Ancient Philosophy 34 (1):75-100.
    I discuss Aristotle's treatment of essence and definition in Metaphysics VII.4. I argue that it is coherent and perfectly in accord with its broader context. His discussion in VII.4 offers, on the one hand, minimal criteria for what counts as definition and essence for whatever kind of object, but also, on the other hand, stronger criteria for a primary sort of definition and essence—and thereby it serves the interest of book VII in pointing to the explanatory power of the essence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Do Real Contradictions Belong to Heraclitus’ Conception of Change? The Anti-cognate Internal Object Gives a Sign.Celso Vieira - 2024 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 26 (2):184-206.
    Heraclitus uses paradoxical language to present the relationship between opposites in his worldview. This mode of expression has generated much controversy. Some take the paradoxes as evidence of a contradictory identity of opposites (Barnes), while others propose a dynamic union through transformation without identity that avoids the contradiction (Graham). By examining B88 and B62, I seek to identify the stronger and weaker points of such readings. The contradictory identity reading thwarts the transformation between opposites. The dynamic reading offers a plausible (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some Types of Abnormal Word-Order in Attic Comedy.K. J. Dover - 1985 - Classical Quarterly 35 (2):324-343.
    On the analogy of the colloquial register in some modern languages, where narrative and argument may be punctuated by oaths and exclamations (sometimes obscene or blasphemous) in order to maintain a high affective level and compel the hearer's attention, it is reasonable to postulate that Attic conversation also was punctuated by oaths, that this ingredient in comic language was drawn from life, and that the comparative frequency of ║ (|)M M(M) Δ in comedy is sufficiently explained thereby. There are obvious (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Socratic Heterodoxy? Ontological Commitment in the Hippias Major.Sean Driscoll - 2024 - Phronesis 69 (1):1-30.
    The question of ontological commitment in Plato’s Hippias Major has been important in disputes over the dialogue’s place in the corpus, its meaning, and its authenticity. But this question seems to have been settled—the Hippias Major is not committed to the ‘forms.’ Such an ontological conclusion has been vigorously defended, but its defenses rest on a problematic meta-ontological framework. This paper suggests a more adequate framework and brings more evidence to the evaluation of the question of ontological commitment in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sobre os múltiplos sentidos de subst'ncia: Nota acerca de Metafísica Z3, 1028b33-34.Raphael Zillig - 2007 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 1 (1).
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On emending and not emending the text of some passages in Aristotle's ethica eudemia.Peter L. P. Simpson - 2013 - Classical Quarterly 63 (2):660-679.
    The text of Aristotle'sEthica Eudemia is often in need of emendation, especially because of the particular fault in the manuscripts of misreading one letter for another or misdividing letters to form words. Scholars have already done fine work in correcting many of these errors, but more needs to be done. A second problem with the text does not have to do with matters of spelling or grammar, but rather with those of philosophical sense. For, as scholars have noted, theEEis marked (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pindar, olympian 2.5–7, text and commentary—with excursions to ‘perictione’, empedocles and euripides’ hippolytus.M. S. Silk - 2020 - Classical Quarterly 70 (2):499-517.
    In 1998, I suggested a new text for a notably corrupt passage in Pindar's Isthmian 5. This article is in effect a sequel to that earlier discussion. In the 1998 article, I proposed, inter alia, that the modern vulgate text of I. 5.58, ἐλπίδων ἔκνισ’ ὄπιν, is indefensible and the product of scribal corruption in antiquity, and that chief among the indefensible products of corruption there is the supposed secular use of ὄπις, as if used to mean something like ‘zeal’. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Alibis (The poetics of Callimachus within the multi-ethnic and expatriate socio-political and cultural context of Ptolemaic Alexandria).Daniel L. Selden - 1998 - Classical Antiquity 17 (2):288.
    This is a general reading of Callimachus' work within the socio-political context of Ptolemaic Alexandria. "Alibis" refers to the constitutionally expatriate nature of the populace and culture established there, which in Callimachus gives rise to a poetics based on the principles of displacement and convergence. Close analysis of a wide variety of passages, drawn principally from the epigrams, Aetia, and Hymns, demonstrates how the "order of the alibi" informs all major aspects of the poet's work, from the lexical make-up of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Writing the Manic Subject: Rhetorical Passivity in Plato's Phaedrus.Robin Reames & Courtney Sloey - 2021 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 54 (1):1-24.
    ABSTRACT This essay questions the reading of Plato's Phaedrus according to which writing is understood as a mechanism of objectivity and critical distance. Plato's denomination of writing as a “pharmakon” indicates a deep ambiguity in his definition of writing—an ambiguity embodied in Phaedrus's written speech. The speech triggers both critical analysis and a simultaneous “rhetorical passivity,” whereby upon hearing the speech Socrates is consumed by a manic power. Although Socrates explicitly decries the detrimental consequences of writing in the Myth of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Colloquium 1.A. W. Price - 1990 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 6 (1):28-33.
  • What do the Arguments in the Protagoras Amount to?Vasilis Politis - 2012 - Phronesis 57 (3):209-239.
    Abstract The main thesis of the paper is that, in the coda to the Protagoras (360e-end), Plato tells us why and with what justification he demands a definition of virtue: namely, in order to resolve a particular aporia . According to Plato's assessment of the outcome of the arguments of the dialogue, the principal question, whether or not virtue can be taught , has, by the end of the dialogue, emerged as articulating an aporia , in that both protagonists, Socrates (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Argumentative Strategies for Interpreting Plato’s Cosmogony: Taurus and the Issue of Literalism in Antiquity.Federico M. Petrucci - 2016 - Phronesis 61 (1):43-59.
    _ Source: _Volume 61, Issue 1, pp 43 - 59 Contemporary debate on Plato’s cosmogony often assumes that the ‘literal’ reading of the _Timaeus_ yields an account of creation, while the view that the cosmos always existed is non-literal. In antiquity, Taurus has been seen as a forerunner of the ‘non-literal’ interpretation. This paper shows, on the contrary, that Taurus’ argument for the sempiternity of the cosmos is a literalist one, relying on a strict linguistic analysis of _Timaeus_ 28b6-8.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Educating Croesus: Talking and Learning in Herodotus' Lydian {Logos.Christopher Pelling - 2006 - Classical Antiquity 25 (1):141-177.
    Two themes, the elusiveness of wisdom and the distortion of speech, are traced through three important scenes of Herodotus' Lydian logos, the meeting of Solon and Croesus , the scene where Cyrus places Croesus on the pyre , and the advice of Croesus to Cyrus to cross the river and fight the Massagetae in their own territory . The paper discusses whether Solon is speaking indirectly at 1.29–33, unable to talk straight to Croesus about his transgressive behavior: if so, that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cratylus 439D3–440C1 : Its texts, its arguments, and why it is not about forms.Simon Noriega-Olmos - 2020 - Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch Fur Antike Und Mittelalter 23 (1):1-32.
    Some interpreters take the arguments at Cratylus 439D3–440C1 to argue for Forms. Some interpreters also believe that these arguments are elliptical or contain lacunae. I accept that the arguments are elliptical. However, I deny that they contain lacunae. I present the most natural construal of the text and argue that it neither trades on Forms nor postulates Forms. To make my case, I show that Cratylus 439D3–440C1 has a modest end, which is to refute a particular notion of flux.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cratylus 439D3–440C1 : Its texts, its arguments, and why it is not about forms.Simon Noriega-Olmos - 2020 - Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch Fur Antike Und Mittelalter 23 (1):1-32.
    Some interpreters take the arguments at Cratylus 439D3–440C1 to argue for Forms. Some interpreters also believe that these arguments are elliptical or contain lacunae. I accept that the arguments are elliptical. However, I deny that they contain lacunae. I present the most natural construal of the text and argue that it neither trades on Forms nor postulates Forms. To make my case, I show that Cratylus 439D3–440C1 has a modest end, which is to refute a particular notion of flux.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Affect and Sensation: Plato’s Embodied Cognition.Ian McCready-Flora - 2018 - Phronesis 63 (2):117-147.
    _ Source: _Volume 63, Issue 2, pp 117 - 147 I argue that Plato, in the _Timaeus_, draws deep theoretical distinctions between sensation and affect, which comprises pleasure, pain, desire and emotion. Sensation is both ‘fine-grained’ and ‘immediate’. Emotions, by contrast, are mediated and coarse-grained. Pleasure and pain are coarse-grained but, in a range of important cases, immediate. The _Theaetetus_ assimilates affect to sensation in a way the _Timaeus_ does not. Smell frustrates Timaeus because it is coarse-grained, although unlike pleasure (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Partaking of Reason in a Way: Aristotle on the Rationality of Human Desire.Duane Long - 2022 - Apeiron 55 (1):35-63.
    Three times in Book 1 chapter 13 of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle says desire partakes of reason in a way. There is a consensus view in the literature about what that claim means: desire has no intrinsic rationality, but can partake of reason by being blindly obedient to the commands of reason. I argue this consensus view is mistaken: for Aristotle, adult human desire has its own intrinsic rationality, and while it is to be obedient to reason, it is not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Sophocles at Patavium (fr. 137 Radt).Matthew Leigh - 1998 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 118:82-100.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Observation Claims and Epistemic Confidence in Aristotle’s Biology.Daryn Lehoux - 2017 - Isis 108 (2):241-258.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Function Argument in the Eudemian Ethics.Roy C. Lee - 2022 - Ancient Philosophy 42 (1):191-214.
    This paper reconstructs the function argument of Aristotle’s Eudemian Ethics 2.1. The argument seeks to define happiness through the method of division; shows that the highest good is better than all four of the goods of the soul, not only two, as commentators have thought; and unlike the Nicomachean argument, makes the highest good definitionally independent of the human function.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Choral Lyric as ““Ritualization””: Poetic Sacrifice and Poetic Ego in Pindar's Sixth Paian.Leslie Kurke - 2005 - Classical Antiquity 24 (1):81-130.
    The ego or speaking subject of Pindar's Sixth Paian is anomalous, as has been acknowledged by many scholars. In a genre whose ego is predominantly choral, the speaking subject at the beginning of Paian 6 differentiates himself from the chorus and confidently analogizes his poetic authority to the prophetic power of Delphi by his self-description as αοίδιμον Πιερίδων προfάταν. I would like to correlate Pindar's exceptional ego in this poem with what has recently emerged as the poem's exceptional performance context. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Supposed Contradiction about Emotion-Arousal in Aristotle's Rhetoric.Jamie Dow - 2007 - Phronesis 52 (4):382 - 402.
    Aristotle, in the Rhetoric, appears to claim both that emotion-arousal has no place in the essential core of rhetorical expertise and that it has an extremely important place as one of three technical kinds of proof. This paper offers an account of how this apparent contradiction can be resolved. The resolution stems from a new understanding of what Rhetoric I. I refers to - not emotions, but set-piece rhetorical devices aimed at manipulating emotions, which do not depend on the facts (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Plato’s Recollection Argument in the Philebus.Naoya Iwata - 2018 - Rhizomata 6 (2):189-212.
    Many scholars have denied that Plato’s argument about desire at Philebus 34c10–35d7 is related to his recollection arguments in the Meno and Phaedo, because it is concerned only with postnatal experiences of pleasure. This paper argues against their denial by showing that the desire argument in question is intended to prove the soul’s possession of innate memory of pleasure. This innateness interpretation will be supported by a close analysis of the Timaeus, where Plato suggests that our inborn desires for food (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • First Wave Feminism: Craftswomen in Plato’s Republic.Emily Hulme - 2022 - Apeiron 55 (4):485-507.
    Ancient Athenian women worked in industries ranging from woolworking and food sales to metalworking and medicine; Socrates’ mother was a midwife. The argument for the inclusion of women in the guardian class must be read in light of this historical reality, not least because it allows us retain an important manuscript reading and construe the passage as relying on an inductive generalization rather than a possibly circular argument. Ultimately, Plato fails to fully capitalize on the resources he has for a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Reply to John Dudley on Aristotle, Physics 2.5, 196b17–21.Giovanna R. Giardina - 2017 - Peitho 8 (1):271-288.
    In this article, I restate the interpretation of Aristotle’s Ph. 2.5, 196b17– 21, which I presented for the first time in my book I fondamenti della causalità naturale. According to my reading, both the things that are due to deliberation and those that are not fall within the group of beings which come to be not for the sake of anything. In his recent book, Aristotle’s Concept of Chance, John Dudley found my interpretation laudable and original but rejected it, opting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O não-ser em Parmênides de Eleia.Nicola Stefano Galgano - 2018 - Trans/Form/Ação 41 (2):9-36.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some Types of Abnormal Word-Order in Attic Comedy.K. J. Dover - 1985 - Classical Quarterly 35 (02):324-.
    On the analogy of the colloquial register in some modern languages, where narrative and argument may be punctuated by oaths and exclamations in order to maintain a high affective level and compel the hearer's attention, it is reasonable to postulate that Attic conversation also was punctuated by oaths, that this ingredient in comic language was drawn from life, and that the comparative frequency of ║ M M Δ in comedy is sufficiently explained thereby. There are obvious affinities between some passages (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Herodotus 1.66 and demosthenes 19.231: The case against ευθηνεομαι / ευθενεομαι.David-Artur Daix - 2020 - Classical Quarterly 70 (1):161-170.
    In Demosthenes’ speech On the False Embassy, we read an obelized infinitive at §231, †εὐθενεῖσθαι†, ‘to be flourishing’, in an imaginary dialogue designed to captivate and persuade the judges through its striking antitheses and dramatic tone: — τί οὖν μετὰ ταῦτα.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Pindaric First Person in Flux.B. G. F. Currie - 2013 - Classical Antiquity 32 (2):243-282.
    This article argues that in Pindar's epinicians first-person statements may occasionally be made in the persona of the chorus and the athletic victor. The speaking persona behind Pindar's first-person statements varies quite widely: from generic, rhetorical poses—a laudator, an aoidos in the rhapsodic tradition (the “bardic first person”), an Everyman (the “first person indefinite”)—to strongly individualized figures: the Theban poet Pindar, the chorus, the victor. The arguable changes in the speaker's persona are not explicitly signalled in the text. This can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Herodotean Kings and Historical Inquiry.Matthew R. Christ - 1994 - Classical Antiquity 13 (2):167-202.
    This article seeks evidence of Herodotus's conception of his historical enterprise in the recurring scenes in which he portrays barbarian kings as inquirers and investigators. Through these scenes-involving most notably Psammetichus, Etearchus, Croesus, Cyrus, Cambyses, Darius, and Xerxes-the historian not only explores the character of autocrats, but also holds up a mirror to his own activity as inquirer. Once we recognize the metahistorical dimension of Herodotus's representation of inquiring kings, we can better understand the scenes in which these figures appear (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Logic of Biological Diversity.Andrea Libero Carbone - 2023 - Apeiron 56 (3):621-642.
    Aristotle’s biology is based on his method of division of animal kinds by multiple differentiae. This results in complex clusters of non-subordinate terms, between which Aristotle seeks to establish universal correlations. The form of these, however, does not correspond to that prescribed by his theory of syllogism. Mereological relations between terms are not linear and quantification is far more complex than the distinction between universal and particular propositions. Thus the axiomatisation of Aristotle’s biology requires a tool designed for analysing such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Discourse and performance: Involvement, visualization and `presence' in Homeric poetry.Egbert J. Bakker - 1993 - Classical Antiquity 12 (1):1-29.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Change, Agency and the Incomplete in Aristotle.Andreas Anagnostopoulos - 2017 - Phronesis 62 (2):170-209.
    Aristotle’s most fundamental distinction between changes and other activities is not that ofMetaphysicsΘ.6, between end-exclusive and end-inclusive activities, but one implicit inPhysics3.1’s definition of change, between the activity of something incomplete and the activity of something complete. Notably, only the latter distinction can account for Aristotle’s view, inPhysics3.3, that ‘agency’—effecting change in something, e.g. teaching—does not qualify strictly as a change. This distinction informsDe Anima2.5 and imparts unity to Aristotle’s extended treatment of change inPhysics3.1-3.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reconstructing Chrysippus’ Cosmological Hypothesis. On Plut. Stoic. rep. 1054c–d.Michele Alessandrelli - 2019 - Elenchos: Rivista di Studi Sul Pensiero Antico 40 (1):67-98.
    Two literal quotations from Chrysippus’ On Possibles, preserved in Plutarch’s On the Contradictions of the Stoics, seem to contradict the Stoic thesis of the isotropy of the void. According to this thesis the void is an infinite undifferentiated expanse whose center is marked by, and coincides with, the position of the world. Since there is nothing else outside the world, the cohesive force that pervades it is sufficient on its own to guarantee the quasi–indestructibility of the trans–cyclical διακόσμησις and the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nota sobre a conjectura de Schwegler em Metafísica E1, 1026a14.Renan Eduardo Stoll - 2022 - Hypnos 48:79-91.
  • Elencuadre de la Pítica IV de Píndaro I.Carmen V. Verde Castro - 2009 - Synthesis (la Plata) 16:167-216.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hesiod and the didactic double.Richard P. Martin - 2004 - Synthesis (la Plata) 11:31-53.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark