Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Modularity need not imply locality: Damaged modules can have nonlocal effects.Edgar Zurif & David Swinney - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):89-90.
  • What counts as local?Andrew W. Young - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):88-89.
  • The localization/distribution distinction in neuropsychology is related to the isomorphism/multiple meaning distinction in cell electrophysiology.Gerald S. Wasserman - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):87-88.
  • The symbolic brain or the invisible hand?René van Hezewijk & Edward H. F. de Haan - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):85-86.
  • Playing Flourens to Fodor's Gall.Tim van Gelder - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):84-84.
  • Prosopagnosia, conscious awareness and the interactive brain.Robert Van Gulick - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):84-85.
  • The functional architecture of visual attention may still be modular.Carlo Umiltà - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):82-83.
  • The imbalance of oculomotor capture in unilateral visual neglect.Stefan Der Stigchevanl & Tanja C. W. Nijboer - 2010 - Consciousness and Cognition 19 (1):186-197.
    Visual neglect has been associated with an imbalance in the level of activity in the saccadic system: activity in the contralesional field is suppressed, which makes target selection unlikely. We recorded eye movements of a patient with hemispatial neglect and a group of healthy participants during an oculomotor distractor paradigm. Results showed that the interfering effects of a distractor were very strong when presented in her ipsilesional visual field. However, when the distractor was presented in her contralesional field, there were (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The imbalance of oculomotor capture in unilateral visual neglect.Stefan Van der Stigchel & Tanja Cw Nijboer - 2010 - Consciousness and Cognition 19 (1):186-197.
  • The real functional architecture is gray, wet and slippery.Steven L. Small - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):81-82.
  • The Concrete Universal and Cognitive Science.Richard Shillcock - 2014 - Axiomathes 24 (1):63-80.
    Cognitive science depends on abstractions made from the complex reality of human behaviour. Cognitive scientists typically wish the abstractions in their theories to be universals, but seldom attend to the ontology of universals. Two sorts of universal, resulting from Galilean abstraction and materialist abstraction respectively, are available in the philosophical literature: the abstract universal—the one-over-many universal—is the universal conventionally employed by cognitive scientists; in contrast, a concrete universal is a material entity that can appear within the set of entities it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Throwing out the neuropsychological data with the locality bathwater?Philip Servos & Elizabeth M. Olds - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):80-81.
  • Locus-pocus.Carlo Semenza - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):80-80.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception and its interactive substrate: Psychophysical linking hypotheses and psychophysical methods.Robert Sekuler - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):79-79.
  • Local and distributed processes in attentional orienting.Michael I. Posner - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):78-79.
  • Parallel distributed processing challenges the strong modularity hypothesis, not the locality assumption.David C. Plaut - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):77-78.
  • Computational Neuropsychology and Bayesian Inference.Thomas Parr, Geraint Rees & Karl J. Friston - 2018 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 12.
  • A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness.J. Kevin O’Regan & Alva Noë - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (5):883-917.
    Many current neurophysiological, psychophysical, and psychological approaches to vision rest on the idea that when we see, the brain produces an internal representation of the world. The activation of this internal representation is assumed to give rise to the experience of seeing. The problem with this kind of approach is that it leaves unexplained how the existence of such a detailed internal representation might produce visual consciousness. An alternative proposal is made here. We propose that seeing is a way of (...)
    Direct download (16 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   732 citations  
  • Computational levels again.Mike Oaksford - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):76-77.
  • Asymmetric Spatial Processing Under Cognitive Load.Lien Naert, Mario Bonato & Wim Fias - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hemispheric Asymmetries in Cognitive Modeling: Connectionist Modeling of Unilateral Visual Neglect.Padraic Monaghan & Richard Shillcock - 2004 - Psychological Review 111 (2):283-308.
  • Distributed locality and large-scale neurocognitive networks.M. Marsel Mesulam - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):74-76.
  • Neuropsychology: Going loco?Rosaleen A. McCarthy - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):73-74.
  • Behavioral Restriction Determines Left Attentional Bias: Preliminary Evidences From COVID-19 Lockdown.Anna Lardone, Patrizia Turriziani, Pierpaolo Sorrentino, Onofrio Gigliotta, Andrea Chirico, Fabio Lucidi & Laura Mandolesi - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    During the COVID-19 lockdown, individuals were forced to remain at home, hence severely limiting the interaction within environmental stimuli, reducing the cognitive load placed on spatial competences. The effects of the behavioral restriction on cognition have been little examined. The present study is aimed at analyzing the effects of lockdown on executive function prominently involved in adapting behavior to new environmental demands. We analyze non-verbal fluency abilities, as indirectly providing a measure of cognitive flexibility to react to spatial changes. Sixteen (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Do neuropsychologists think in terms of interactive models?Marcel Kinsbourne - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):72-73.
  • Go with the flow but mind the details.Glyn W. Humphreys & M. Jane Riddoch - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):71-72.
  • No threat to modularity.Yosef Grodzinsky & Uri Hadar - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):70-71.
  • Clarifying the locality assumption.Clark Glymour - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):69-70.
  • Neuropsychological inference with an interactive brain: A critique of the “locality” assumption.Martha J. Farah - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):43-61.
    When cognitive neuropsychologists make inferences about the functional architecture of the normal mind from selective cognitive impairments they generally assume that the effects of brain damage are local, that is, that the nondamaged components of the architecture continue to function as they did before the damage. This assumption follows from the view that the components of the functional architecture are modular, in the sense of being informationally encapsulated. In this target article it is argued that this “locality” assumption is probably (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Interactions on the interactive brain.Martha J. Farah - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):90-104.
    When cognitive neuropsychologists make inferences about the functional architecture of the normal mind from selective cognitive impairments they generally assume that the effects of brain damage are local, that is, that the nondamaged components of the architecture continue to function as they did before the damage. This assumption follows from the view that the components of the functional architecture are modular, in the sense of being informationally encapsulated. In this target article it is argued that this “locality” assumption is probably (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neurocomputing and modularity.Joachim Diederich - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):68-69.
  • Further advantages of abandoning the locality assumption in face recognition.Jules Davidoff & Bernard Renault - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):68-68.
  • Modularity, abstractness and the interactive brain.James M. Clark - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):67-68.
  • Modularity, interaction and connectionist neuropsychology.Nick Chater - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):66-67.
  • Casting one's net too widely?D. P. Carey & A. D. Milner - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):65-66.
  • Locality, modularity and numerical cognition.Jamie I. D. Campbell - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):63-64.
  • Discarding locality assumptions: Problems and prospects.Ruth Campbell - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):64-65.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Regional specialities.Brian Butterworth - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):63-63.
  • Local representations without the locality assumption.A. Mike Burton & Vicki Bruce - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):62-63.
  • Simulating nonlocal systems: Rules of the game.John A. Bullinaria - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):61-62.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark