Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. From individual to social counterintuitiveness: how layers of innovation weave together to form multilayered tapestries of human cultures.M. Afzal Upal - 2011 - Mind and Society 10 (1):79-96.
    The emerging field of cognition and culture has had some success in explaining the spread of counterintuitive religious concepts around the world. However, researchers have been reluctant to extend its findings to explain the widespread occurrence of culturally counterintuitive ideas in general. This article develops a broader notion of social counterintuitiveness to include ideas that violate shared expectations of a group of people and argues that the notion of social counterintuitiveness is more crucial to explaining cultural success of surprising ideas (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Seeing the unseen: Second-order correlation learning in 7- to 11-month-olds.Yevdokiya Yermolayeva & David H. Rakison - 2016 - Cognition 152 (C):87-100.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some questions on optimal inbreeding and biologically adaptive culture.George C. Williams - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):116-116.
  • Culture analyzed in the mode of the natural sciences.Edward O. Wilson - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):116-117.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are there really two types of learning?Yorick Wilks - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):671-671.
  • The hard questions about noninductive learning remain unanswered.Eric Wanner - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):670-670.
  • Conceptual Change from the Framework Theory Side of the Fence.Stella Vosniadou & Irini Skopeliti - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (7):1427-1445.
  • Incest, genes, and culture.Pierre L. van den Berghe - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):117-123.
  • Human inbreeding avoidance: Culture in nature.Pierre L. van den Berghe - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):91-102.
    Much clinical and ethnographic evidence suggests that humans, like many other organisms, are selected to avoid close inbreeding because of the fitness costs of inbreeding depression. The proximate mechanism of human inbreeding avoidance seems to be precultural, and to involve the interaction of genetic predispositions and environmental conditions. As first suggested by E. Westermarck, and supported by evidence from Israeli kibbutzim, Chinese sim-pua marriage, and much convergent ethnographic and clinical evidence, humans negatively imprint on intimate associates during a critical period (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • Rejecting induction: Using occam's razor too soon.J. T. Tolliver - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):669-670.
  • Stability and variation in human evolution.Lionel Tiger - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):115-116.
  • The pragmatics of induction.Paul Thagard - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):668-669.
  • Healing, Mental Energy in the Physics Classroom: Energy Conceptions and Trust in Complementary and Alternative Medicine in Grade 10–12 Students. [REVIEW]Annika M. Svedholm & Marjaana Lindeman - 2013 - Science & Education 22 (3):677-694.
  • Salvaging parts of the “classical theory” of categorization.Dan Sperber - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):668-668.
  • What are the mechanisms of coevolution?Peter K. Smith - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):114-115.
  • Category differences/automaticity.Edward E. Smith - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):667-667.
  • Theory-laden concepts: Great, but what is the next step?Charles P. Shimp - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):666-667.
  • A coup de grace to cultural relativism.Joseph Shepher - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):114-114.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intension and representation: Quine’s indeterminacy thesis revisited.Itay Shani - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (4):415 – 440.
    This paper re-addresses Quine's indeterminacy of translation/inscrutability of reference thesis, as a problem for cognitive theories of content. In contradistinction with Quine's behavioristic semantics, theories of meaning, or content, in the cognitivist tradition endorse intentional realism, and are prone to be unsympathetic to Quine's thesis. Yet, despite this fundamental difference, I argue that they are just as vulnerable to the indeterminacy. I then argue that the vulnerability is rooted in a theoretical commitment tacitly shared with Quine, namely, the commitment to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The learning of function and the function of learning.Roger C. Schank, Gregg C. Collins & Lawrence E. Hunter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):672-686.
  • Transcending inductive category formation in learning.Roger C. Schank, Gregg C. Collins & Lawrence E. Hunter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):639-651.
    The inductive category formation framework, an influential set of theories of learning in psychology and artificial intelligence, is deeply flawed. In this framework a set of necessary and sufficient features is taken to define a category. Such definitions are not functionally justified, are not used by people, and are not inducible by a learning system. Inductive theories depend on having access to all and only relevant features, which is not only impossible but begs a key question in learning. The crucial (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Is van den Berghe in a new paradigm?Michael Ruse - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):113-114.
  • Cognisance and cognitive science. Part two: Towards an empirical psychology of cognisance.James Russell - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (2):165-201.
    Abstract In the first part of this essay (Russell, 1988a) I argued that ?cognisance? (roughly: a subject's knowledge of his relation to the physical world as an experiencer of it) cannot be explained in terms of a syntactic theory of mind, due to the ?referential? and ?holistic? nature of this knowledge. The syntactic account of the higher mental functions is immediately intelligible to us due to its derivation from computer technology, so this would not appear to be a happy result (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A simple model from a powerful framework that spans levels of analysis.Timothy T. Rogers & James L. McClelland - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6):729-749.
    The commentaries reflect three core themes that pertain not just to our theory, but to the enterprise of connectionist modeling more generally. The first concerns the relationship between a cognitive theory and an implemented computer model. Specifically, how does one determine, when a model departs from the theory it exemplifies, whether the departure is a useful simplification or a critical flaw? We argue that the answer to this question depends partially upon the model's intended function, and we suggest that connectionist (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Approaches, assumptions, and goals in modeling cognitive behavior.Richard E. Pastore & David G. Payne - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):665-666.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The debate between current versions of covariation and mechanism approaches to causal inference.George L. Newsome - 2003 - Philosophical Psychology 16 (1):87 – 107.
    Current psychological research on causal inference is dominated by two basic approaches: the covariation approach and the mechanism approach. This article reviews these two approaches, evaluates the contributions and limitations of each approach, and suggests how these approaches might be integrated into a more comprehensive framework. Covariation theorists assume that cognizers infer causal relations from conditional probabilities computed over samples of multiple events, but they do not provide an adequate account of how cognizers constrain their search for candidate causes and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Patterns.Norton Nelkin - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (1):56-87.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The psychology of category learning: Current status and future prospect.Gregory L. Murphy - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):664-665.
  • Of what use categories?Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):663-664.
  • Inbreeding, cousin marriage, and social solidarity.Umberto Melotti - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):112-113.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A psychologist's perspective on incest avoidance behavior.Karin C. Meiselman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):112-112.
  • Constraints and Preferences in Inductive Learning: An Experimental Study of Human and Machine Performance.Douglas L. Medin, William D. Wattenmaker & Ryszard S. Michalski - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (3):299-339.
    The paper examines constraints and preferences employed by people in learning decision rules from preclassified examples. Results from four experiments with human subjects were analyzed and compared with artificial intelligence (AI) inductive learning programs. The results showed the people's rule inductions tended to emphasize category validity (probability of some property, given a category) more than cue validity (probability that an entity is a member of a category given that it has some property) to a greater extent than did the AI (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Letting structure emerge: connectionist and dynamical systems approaches to cognition.James L. McClelland, Matthew M. Botvinick, David C. Noelle, David C. Plaut, Timothy T. Rogers, Mark S. Seidenberg & Linda B. Smith - 2010 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14 (8):348-356.
  • Emergence in Cognitive Science.James L. McClelland - 2010 - Topics in Cognitive Science 2 (4):751-770.
    The study of human intelligence was once dominated by symbolic approaches, but over the last 30 years an alternative approach has arisen. Symbols and processes that operate on them are often seen today as approximate characterizations of the emergent consequences of sub- or nonsymbolic processes, and a wide range of constructs in cognitive science can be understood as emergents. These include representational constructs (units, structures, rules), architectural constructs (central executive, declarative memory), and developmental processes and outcomes (stages, sensitive periods, neurocognitive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Making sense of domain specificity.Eric Margolis & Stephen Laurence - 2023 - Cognition 240 (C):105583.
    The notion of domain specificity plays a central role in some of the most important debates in cognitive science. Yet, despite the widespread reliance on domain specificity in recent theorizing in cognitive science, this notion remains elusive. Critics have claimed that the notion of domain specificity can't bear the theoretical weight that has been put on it and that it should be abandoned. Even its most steadfast proponents have highlighted puzzles and tensions that arise once one tries to go beyond (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The incestuous mind.Charles J. Lumsden - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):112-112.
  • Do humans maximize their inclusive fitness?Frank B. Livingstone - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):110-111.
  • When explanation is too hard (or understanding hijacking for novices).Michael Lebowitz - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):662-663.
  • The Trouble with Consciousness.Charles D. Laughlin - 1992 - Anthropology of Consciousness 3 (3-4):1-2.
    The purposes of this paper are twofold: first, I wish to correct a systematic bias in Husserlian transcendental phenomenology. This bias is in favor of intuition of essences of meaning and against the intuition of essences of sensation. This bias is explained as a product of Husserl's mind-body dualism. Second, I suggest the possibility of a neurophenomenology from a biogenetic structural point of view. This neurophenomenology merges the knowledge of essences derived from mature contemplation with knowledge of the structures of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sexual rivalry in human inbreeding or adaptive cooperation?Chet S. Lancaster - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):109-110.
  • New failures to learn.Barbara Landau - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):660-661.
  • Induction and explanation: Complementary models of learning.Pat Langley - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):661-662.
  • A case for less selfing and more outbreeding in reviewing the literature.Michael E. Lamb & Eric L. Charnov - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):109-109.
  • Induction and probability.Henry E. Kyburg - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):660-660.
  • Second-generation AI theories of learning.David Kirsh - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):658-659.
  • Structured statistical models of inductive reasoning.Charles Kemp & Joshua B. Tenenbaum - 2009 - Psychological Review 116 (1):20-58.
  • The more things change…: Metamorphoses and conceptual structure.Michael H. Kelly & Frank C. Keil - 1985 - Cognitive Science 9 (4):403-416.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Clarity, generality, and efficiency in models of learning: Wringing the MOP.Kevin T. Kelly - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):657-658.
  • Two dogmas of conceptual empiricism: implications for hybrid models of the structure of knowledge.Frank Keil - 1998 - Cognition 65 (2-3):103-135.
  • Constraints on Constraints: Surveying the Epigenetic Landscape.Frank C. Keil - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14 (1):135-168.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations