Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Ethics of Policing and Imprisonment.Molly Gardner & Michael Weber (eds.) - 2018 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This volume considers the ethics of policing and imprisonment, focusing particularly on mass incarceration and police shootings in the United States. The contributors consider the ways in which non-ideal features of the criminal justice system―features such as the prevalence of guns in America, political pressures, considerations of race and gender, and the lived experiences of people in jails and prisons―impinge upon conclusions drawn from more idealized models of punishment and law enforcement. There are a number of common themes running throughout (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Preface to Social Theory of Property Rights.Ross Zucker - 1995 - Ratio Juris 8 (2):199-211.
    In the history of liberal theories of property, the predominant model deduces a right to highly unequal amounts of property from a premise that the person is primarily independent and self‐determined. But modem social theory, communitarianism and critical legal theory have generated strong support for an alternative premise of social self‐determination of the person. These theories have not, however, adequately explored the logical implications of social personality for the justifiable degree of equality of income under property right. This study reasons (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Rule of Law in Contemporary Liberal Theory.Jeremy Waldron - 1989 - Ratio Juris 2 (1):79-96.
    Existing accounts of the Rule of Law are inadequate and require fleshing out. The main value of the ideal of rule of law for liberal political theory lies in the notion of predictability, which is essential to individual autonomy. The author examines this connection and argues that conservative theories of rule of law claim too much. Liberal theory equates the rule of law with legality, which is only one of the elements necessary for a just social order.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Executive as Executioner and the Informed Governance Principle.Martin Skladany - 2009 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (3):289-300.
    An executive ought to be as informed as possible about the needs and preferences of her constituency and about the most important policy issues that her constituency confronts. This ethical duty, referred to as the informed governance principle, requires that an executive who is not opposed to the death penalty personally carry out at least one execution of a death row inmate. Having an executive act as executioner, even if just once, could also help citizens reflect upon their personal ethical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In Force Without Significance: Kantian Nihilism and Agamben’s Critique of Law.Daniel McLoughlin - 2009 - Law and Critique 20 (3):245-257.
    In Homo Sacer, Giorgio Agamben makes the claim that Kant’s moral philosophy is prophetic of legal nihilism and modern totalitarianism. In doing so, he draws an implicit parallel between Kantian ethics of respect and autonomy, and the authoritarian constitutional theory of Carl Schmitt. This paper elucidates and evaluates this claim through an analysis of Agamben’s assertion that the legal condition of modernity is a nihilistic law that is ‘in force without significance’. I argue that the theoretical continuity between totalitarianism and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Retributive parsimony.Richard L. Lippke - 2009 - Res Publica 15 (4):377-395.
    Retributive approaches to the justification of legal punishment are often thought to place exacting and unattractive demands on state officials, requiring them to expend scarce public resources on apprehending and punishing all offenders strictly in accordance with their criminal ill deserts. Against this caricature of the theory, I argue that retributivists can urge parsimony in the use of punishment. After clarifying what parsimony consists in, I show how retributivists can urge reductions in the use of punishment in order to conserve (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Consequentialist Motives for Punishment Signal Trustworthiness.Nathan A. Dhaliwal, Daniel P. Skarlicki, JoAndrea Hoegg & Michael A. Daniels - 2020 - Journal of Business Ethics 176 (3):451-466.
    Upholding cooperative norms via punishment is of central importance in organizations. But what effect does punishing have on the reputation of the punisher? Although previous research shows third parties can garner reputational benefits for punishing transgressors who violate social norms, we proposed that such reputational benefits can vary based on the perceived motive for the punishment. In Studies 1 and 2, we found that individuals who endorsed a consequentialist (versus deontological) motive for punishing were seen as more trustworthy. In Study (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consequentialist Motives for Punishment Signal Trustworthiness.Nathan A. Dhaliwal, Daniel P. Skarlicki, JoAndrea Hoegg & Michael A. Daniels - 2020 - Journal of Business Ethics 176 (3):451-466.
    Upholding cooperative norms via punishment is of central importance in organizations. But what effect does punishing have on the reputation of the punisher? Although previous research shows third parties can garner reputational benefits for punishing transgressors who violate social norms, we proposed that such reputational benefits can vary based on the perceived motive for the punishment. In Studies 1 and 2, we found that individuals who endorsed a consequentialist motive for punishing were seen as more trustworthy. In Study 3, the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Choice of Evils: In Search of a Viable Rationale.Vera Bergelson - 2012 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3):289-305.
    The defense of necessity, also known as the “choice of evils,” reflects popular moral intuitions and common sense: sometimes, breaking the rules is the right—indeed, the only—thing to do in order to avoid a greater evil. Citing a classic example, mountain climbers may break into a cabin to wait out a deadly snow storm and appropriate the owner’s provisions because their property violations are a lesser evil compared to the loss of life. At the same time, this defense contradicts the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant'in ahlak metafiziğinde evrenselliğin hukuki çözümlemesi.Doğuhan Murat Yücel - 2018 - Ethos: Dialogues in Philosophy and Social Sciences 11 (1).
    Hukukun başlıca sorunları olan genellik ve geçerlilik Immanuel Kant’ın evrensel yasa arayışını incelemeyi gerektirmektedir. Kant evrensel ilkeleri ararken hukuka dair belirlemeler yapmaktadır. Bu çalışmada hak ve hukuk kavramları Kant’ın kapsayıcı ve bütünleştirici sisteminde tahlil edilmektedir. Ahlak Metafiziği’nin Temellendirilmesi eserinde temeller görülürken Ahlak Metafiziği eserinde hakka ve yasal düzenlere dair bir doktrin kurulmaktadır. Kant’ın ideal sisteminde yasal mevzuat değil yasaların temellendiği ilkelerin belirlenmesi esastır. Bu belirleme aynen ahlak yasasında olduğu gibi sonuçlarla ilgilenmez. Bir eylemin sonucunun iyi olup olmaması sorun teşkil etmez. (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant's rejection of the right of revolution.Pohľad Za Hranice - 2009 - Filozofia 64 (6):592.
  • Punishment and Democratic Rights: A Case Study in Non-Ideal Penal Theory.Steve Swartzer - 2018 - In Molly Gardner & Michael Weber (eds.), The Ethics of Policing and Imprisonment. pp. 7-37.
    In the United States, convicted offenders frequently lose the right to vote, at least temporarily. Drawing on the common observation that citizens of color lose democratic rights at disproportionately high rates, this chapter argues that this punishment is problematic in non-ideal societies because of the way in which it diminishes the political power of marginalized groups and threatens to reproduce patterns of domination and subordination, when they occur. This chapter then uses the case of penal disenfranchisement to illustrate how idealized (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Subject in politics and justice.Kim Sang Ong-Van-Cung - 2011 - Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad Del Norte 13:10-25.
    Normal 0 21 false false false ES-CO X-NONE X-NONE MicrosoftInternetExplorer4 In this paper we study the Kantian conception of punishment in the Metaphysics of Morals. We look at Foucault’s reformulation of the right to punish which is mostly a critique of the kantian conception. Then we introduce the conception of restorative justice grounded on the social ideal of recognition, which corrects certain aspects of the Kantian conception, but gives to justice its status of an institution rather than being a critique (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark