Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Hyperintensionality and Normativity.Federico L. G. Faroldi - 2019 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    Presenting the first comprehensive, in-depth study of hyperintensionality, this book equips readers with the basic tools needed to appreciate some of current and future debates in the philosophy of language, semantics, and metaphysics. After introducing and explaining the major approaches to hyperintensionality found in the literature, the book tackles its systematic connections to normativity and offers some contributions to the current debates. The book offers undergraduate and graduate students an essential introduction to the topic, while also helping professionals in related (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Relationships between obligations and actions in the context of institutional agents, human agents or software agents.Robert Demolombe - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 19 (2-3):99-115.
    The paper presents a logical framework for the representation of interactions between institutional agents, human agents and software agents. A case study is used to analyze how obligations on institutional agents are “propagated” to human and software agents, and how actions performed by these agents count as actions that satisfy the obligations imposed to institutional agents. It is shown that the relationship between the different kinds of obligations and actions can be represented in terms of the concept of “count as” (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Normative Multiagent Approach To Requirements Engineering.Serena Villata - 2010 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 18 (1):245-274.
    In this paper we present a new model for the requirements analysis of a system. This is a new model based on the multiagent systems paradigm with the aim to support the requirements analysis phase of systems design. This model offers a structured approach to requirements analysis, based on conceptual models defined following a visual modeling language, called dependence networks. The main elements of this visual language are the agents with their goals, capabilities and facts, similarly to the TROPOS methodology (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Collective acceptance and collective social notions.Raimo Tuomela & Wolfgang Balzer - 1998 - Synthese 117 (2):175-205.
  • Identifying prohibition norms in agent societies.Bastin Tony Roy Savarimuthu, Stephen Cranefield, Maryam A. Purvis & Martin K. Purvis - 2013 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 21 (1):1 - 46.
    In normative multi-agent systems, the question of “how an agent identifies norms in an open agent society” has not received much attention. This paper aims at addressing this question. To this end, this paper proposes an architecture for norm identification for an agent. The architecture is based on observation of interactions between agents. This architecture enables an autonomous agent to identify prohibition norms in a society using the prohibition norm identification (PNI) algorithm. The PNI algorithm uses association rule mining, a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Henning herrestad, formal theories of rights.Giovanni Sartor - 2000 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 8 (1):93-100.
  • Fundamental legal concepts: A formal and teleological characterisation. [REVIEW]Giovanni Sartor - 2006 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 14 (1-2):101-142.
    We shall introduce a set of fundamental legal concepts, providing a definition of each of them. This set will include, besides the usual deontic modalities (obligation, prohibition and permission), the following notions: obligative rights (rights related to other’s obligations), permissive rights, erga-omnes rights, normative conditionals, liability rights, different kinds of legal powers, potestative rights (rights to produce legal results), result-declarations (acts intended to produce legal determinations), and sources of the law.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Irreducibility of Personal Obligation.Jacob Ross - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (3):307 - 323.
    It is argued that claims about personal obligation (of the form "s ought to 0") cannot be reduced to claims about impersonal obligation (of the form "it ought to be the case that p"). The most common attempts at such a reduction are shown to have unacceptable implications in cases involving a plurality of agents. It is then argued that similar problems will face any attempt to reduce personal obligation to impersonal obligation.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A Formal Characterisation of Hamblin’s Action-State Semantics.Chris Reed & Timothy J. Norman - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (4):415 - 448.
    Hamblin's Action-State Semantics provides a sound philosophical foundation for understanding the character of the imperative. Taking this as our inspiration, in this paper we present a logic of action, which we call ST, that captures the clear ontological distinction between being responsible for the achievement of a state of affairs and being responsible for the performance of an action. We argue that a relativised modal logic of type RT founded upon a ternary relation over possible worlds integrated with a basic (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Formal Characterisation of Hamblin’s Action-State Semantics.Chris Reed & Timothy J. Norman - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (4):415-448.
    Hamblin’s Action-State Semantics provides a sound philosophical foundation for understanding the character of the imperative. Taking this as our inspiration, in this paper we present a logic of action, which we call ST, that captures the clear ontological distinction between being responsible for the achievement of a state of affairs and being responsible for the performance of an action. We argue that a relativised modal logic of type RT founded upon a ternary relation over possible worlds integrated with a basic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Some remarks on performatives in the law.Lennart Åqvist - 2003 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 11 (2-3):105-124.
    This paper contains an analysis of performatives with special attention to performatives in the law. It deals with the possibility to recognise performativity by means of a grammatical-syntactic criterion, the self-verifying and norm-promulgating character of legal performatives, an analysis of the effects of performatives by means of causal logic, the different forms of performativity and a theory of promise-performatives.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Law and logic: A review from an argumentation perspective.Henry Prakken & Giovanni Sartor - 2015 - Artificial Intelligence 227 (C):214-245.
  • The open agent society: retrospective and prospective views.Jeremy Pitt & Alexander Artikis - 2015 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 23 (3):241-270.
    It is now more than ten years since the EU FET project ALFEBIITE finished, during which its researchers made original and distinctive contributions to (inter alia) formal models of trust, model-checking, and action logics. ALFEBIITE was also a highly inter-disciplinary project, with partners from computer science, philosophy, cognitive science and law. In this paper, we reflect on the interaction between computer scientists and information and IT lawyers on the idea of the ‘open agent society’. This inspired a programme of research (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The pursuit of computational justice in open systems.Jeremy Pitt, Dídac Busquets & Régis Riveret - 2015 - AI and Society 30 (3):359-378.
    Many open networks, distributed computing systems, and infrastructure management systems face a common problem: how to distribute a collectivised set of resources amongst a set of autonomous agents of heterogenous provenance. One approach is for the agents themselves to self-organise the allocation of resources with respect to a set of agreed conventional rules; but given an allocation scheme which maps resources to those agents and a set of rules for determining that allocation scheme, some natural questions arise—Is this allocation fair? (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Integrating social power into the decision-making of cognitive agents.Gonçalo Pereira, Rui Prada & Pedro A. Santos - 2016 - Artificial Intelligence 241 (C):1-44.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A logic of delegation.Timothy J. Norman & Chris Reed - 2010 - Artificial Intelligence 174 (1):51-71.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Agential Obligation as Non-Agential Personal Obligation plus Agency.Paul McNamara - 2004 - Journal of Applied Logic 2 (1):117-152.
    I explore various ways of integrating the framework for predeterminism, agency, and ability in[P.McNamara, Nordic J. Philos. Logic 5 (2)(2000) 135] with a framework for obligations. However,the agential obligation operator explored here is defined in terms of a non-agential yet personal obligation operator and a non-deontic (and non-normal) agency operator. This is contrary to the main current trend, which assumes statements of personal obligation always take agential complements. Instead, I take the basic form to be an agent’s being obligated to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Ownership: A case study in the representation of legal concepts. [REVIEW]L. Thorne McCarty - 2002 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 10 (1-3):173-190.
    This article is an exercise in computational jurisprudence. It seems clear thatthe field of AI and Law should draw upon the insights of legal philosophers,whenever possible. But can the computational perspective offer anything inreturn? I will explore this question by focusing on the concept of OWNERSHIP,which has been debated in the jurisprudential literature for centuries. Althoughthe intellectual currents here flow mostly in one direction – from legal philosophy to AI – I will show that there are also some insights to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Understanding Hohfeld and Formalizing Legal Rights: The Hohfeldian Conceptions and Their Conditional Consequences.Réka Markovich - 2020 - Studia Logica 108 (1):129-158.
    Hohfeld’s analysis on the different types of rights and duties is highly influential in analytical legal theory, and it is considered as a fundamental theory in AI&Law and normative multi-agent systems. Yet a century later, the formalization of this theory remains, in various ways, unresolved. In this paper I provide a formal analysis of how the working of a system containing Hohfeldian rights and duties can be delineated. This formalization starts from using the same tools as the classical ones by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Electronic institutions for B2B: dynamic normative environments. [REVIEW]Henrique Lopes Cardoso & Eugénio Oliveira - 2008 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 16 (1):107-128.
    The regulation of the activity of multiple autonomous entities represented in a multi-agent system, in environments with no central design (and thus with no cooperative assumption), is gaining much attention in the research community. Approaches to this concern include the use of norms in so-called normative multi-agent systems and the development of electronic institution frameworks. In this paper we describe our approach towards the development of an electronic institution providing an enforceable normative environment. Within this environment, institutional services are provided (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Stratification of normative systems with intermediaries.Lars Lindahl & Jan Odelstad - 2011 - Journal of Applied Logic 9 (2):113-136.
  • Normative positions within an algebraic approach to normative systems.Lars Lindahl & Jan Odelstad - 2004 - Journal of Applied Logic 2 (1):63-91.
  • Legal Power: The Basic Definition.Lars Lindahl & David Reidhav - 2017 - Ratio Juris 30 (2):158-185.
    The concept of legal power is important in the law since, with regard to actions having legal effect, the “exercise of legal power” delimits those actions for which manifestation of intention to achieve a legal effect is essential for the effect to ensue. The paper proposes a definition that captures this feature of legal power and marks it off from “direct effect,” as well as from permissibility and practical ability to achieve the legal effect. This analysis of power is limited (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intermediaries and intervenients in normative systems.Lars Lindahl & Jan Odelstad - 2008 - Journal of Applied Logic 6 (2):229-250.
  • The open agent society as a platform for the user-friendly information society.Jeremy Pitt - 2005 - AI and Society 19 (2):123-158.
    A thematic priority of the European Union’s Framework V research and development programme was the creation of a user-friendly information society which met the needs of citizens and enterprises. In practice, though, for example in the case of on-line digital music, the needs of citizens and enterprises may be in conflict. This paper proposes to leverage the appearance of ‘intelligence’ in the platform layer of a layered communications architecture to avoid such conflicts in similar applications in the future. The key (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Constitutive Rules, Language, and Ontology.Frank Hindriks - 2009 - Erkenntnis 71 (2):253-275.
    It is a commonplace within philosophy that the ontology of institutions can be captured in terms of constitutive rules. What exactly such rules are, however, is not well understood. They are usually contrasted to regulative rules: constitutive rules (such as the rules of chess) make institutional actions possible, whereas regulative rules (such as the rules of etiquette) pertain to actions that can be performed independently of such rules. Some, however, maintain that the distinction between regulative and constitutive rules is merely (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Organizational structure and responsibility: An analysis in a dynamic logic of organized collective agency.Davide Grossi, Lambèr Royakkers & Frank Dignum - 2007 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 15 (3):223-249.
    Aim of the present paper is to provide a formal characterization of various different notions of responsibility within groups of agents (Who did that? Who gets the blame? Who is accountable for that? etc.). To pursue this aim, the papers proposes an organic analysis of organized collective agency by tackling the issues of organizational structure, role enactment, organizational activities, task-division and task-allocation. The result consists in a semantic framework based on dynamic logic in which all these concepts can be represented (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Norms as ascriptions of violations: An analysis in modal logic.Davide Grossi - 2011 - Journal of Applied Logic 9 (2):95-112.
  • On the Axiomatisation of Elgesem's Logic of Agency and Ability.Guido Governatori & Antonino Rotolo - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (4):403-431.
    In this paper we show that the Hilbert system of agency and ability presented by Dag Elgesem is incomplete with respect to the intended semantics. We argue that completeness result may be easily regained. Finally, we shortly discuss some issues related to the philosophical intuition behind his approach. This is done by examining Elgesem's modal logic of agency and ability using semantics with different flavours.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A computational framework for institutional agency.Guido Governatori & Antonino Rotolo - 2008 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 16 (1):25-52.
    This paper provides a computational framework, based on defeasible logic, to capture some aspects of institutional agency. Our background is Kanger-Lindahl-Pörn account of organised interaction, which describes this interaction within a multi-modal logical setting. This work focuses in particular on the notions of counts-as link and on those of attempt and of personal and direct action to realise states of affairs. We show how standard defeasible logic (DL) can be extended to represent these concepts: the resulting system preserves some basic (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Free choice permission, legitimization and relating semantics.Daniela Glavaničová, Tomasz Jarmużek, Mateusz Klonowski & Piotr Kulicki - forthcoming - Logic Journal of the IGPL.
    In this paper, we apply relating semantics to the widely discussed problem of free choice between permitted actions or situations in normative systems. Leaving aside contexts in which the free choice principle is obviously unacceptable or uncontroversially valid, we concentrate on free choice for explicit permissions. In order to construct a formal representation of explicit permissions, we introduce a special constant, $\texttt {permit}$, which is analogous to the constant $\texttt {violation}$ used in the Andersonian–Kangerian approach to deontic logic with respect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Normative autonomy and normative co-ordination: Declarative power, representation, and mandate. [REVIEW]Jonathan Gelati, Antonino Rotolo, Giovanni Sartor & Guido Governatori - 2004 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 12 (1-2):53-81.
    In this paper we provide a formal analysis of the idea of normative co-ordination. We argue that this idea is based on the assumption that agents can achieve flexible co-ordination by conferring normative positions to other agents. These positions include duties, permissions, and powers. In particular, we explain the idea of declarative power, which consists in the capacity of the power-holder of creating normative positions, involving other agents, simply by proclaiming such positions. In addition, we account also for the concepts (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Artificial institutions: A model of institutional reality for open multiagent systems. [REVIEW]Nicoletta Fornara, Francesco Viganò, Mario Verdicchio & Marco Colombetti - 2008 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 16 (1):89-105.
    Software agents’ ability to interact within different open systems, designed by different groups, presupposes an agreement on an unambiguous definition of a set of concepts, used to describe the context of the interaction and the communication language the agents can use. Agents’ interactions ought to allow for reliable expectations on the possible evolution of the system; however, in open systems interacting agents may not conform to predefined specifications. A possible solution is to define interaction environments including a normative component, with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Research in progress: report on the ICAIL 2017 doctoral consortium.Maria Dymitruk, Réka Markovich, Rūta Liepiņa, Mirna El Ghosh, Robert van Doesburg, Guido Governatori & Bart Verheij - 2018 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 26 (1):49-97.
    This paper arose out of the 2017 international conference on AI and law doctoral consortium. There were five students who presented their Ph.D. work, and each of them has contributed a section to this paper. The paper offers a view of what topics are currently engaging students, and shows the diversity of their interests and influences.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Dynamic Logic of Legal Competences.Huimin Dong & Olivier Roy - 2021 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (4):701-724.
    We propose a new formalization of legal competences, and in particular for the Hohfeldian categories of power and immunity, through a deontic reinterpretation of dynamic epistemic logic. We argue that this logic explicitly captures the norm-changing character of legal competences while providing a sophisticated reduction of the latter to static normative positions. The logic is completely axiomatizable, and we apply it to a concrete case in German contract law to illustrate that it can capture the distinction between legal ability and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Communicating open systems.Mark dʼInverno, Michael Luck, Pablo Noriega, Juan A. Rodriguez-Aguilar & Carles Sierra - 2012 - Artificial Intelligence 186 (C):38-94.
  • The representation of legal contracts.Aspassia Daskalopulu & Marek Sergot - 1997 - AI and Society 11 (1-2):6-17.
    The paper outlines ongoing research on logic-based tools for the analysis and representation of legal contracts, of the kind frequently encountered in large-scale engineering projects and complex, long-term trading agreements. We consider both contract formation and contract performance, in each case identifying the representational issues and the prospects for providing automated support tools.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reasoning about constitutive norms in BDI agents.N. Criado, E. Argente, P. Noriega & V. Botti - 2014 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 22 (1):66-93.
  • Distant Causation in C+.Robert Craven & Marek Sergot - 2005 - Studia Logica 79 (1):73-96.
    The action language C+ of Giunchiglia, Lee, Lifschitz, McCain and Turner is a high-level, logical formalism for the representation of domains involving action and change. However, one cannot directly express relationships which hold between states more than one time-step distant, or even say that one action determines another at the next time. We present C+timed, a generalization of C+ which removes these limitations. As for C+, translations to the language of causal theories are given. We also define a new kind (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Prescribed mental attitudes in goal-adoption and Norm-adoption.Cristiano Castelfranchi - 1999 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 7 (1):37-50.
    The general aim of this work is to show the importance of the adressee's mind as planned by the author of a speech act or of a norm; in particular, how important are the expected motivations for goal adoption. We show that speech acts differ from one another for the different motivations the speaker is attempting to obtain from the hearer. The description of the participants' social positions is not sufficient. Important conflicts can arise which are not relative to what (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Normal = Normative? The role of intelligent agents in norm innovation.Marco Campenní, Giulia Andrighetto, Federico Cecconi & Rosaria Conte - 2009 - Mind and Society 8 (2):153-172.
    The necessity to model the mental ingredients of norm compliance is a controversial issue within the study of norms. So far, the simulation-based study of norm emergence has shown a prevailing tendency to model norm conformity as a thoughtless behavior, emerging from social learning and imitation rather than from specific, norm-related mental representations. In this paper, the opposite stance—namely, a view of norms as hybrid, two-faceted phenomena, including a behavioral/social and an internal/mental side—is taken. Such a view is aimed at (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Value-based argumentation for justifying compliance.Brigitte Burgemeestre, Joris Hulstijn & Yao-Hua Tan - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 19 (2-3):149-186.
    Compliance is often achieved ‘by design’ through a coherent system of controls consisting of information systems and procedures. This system-based control requires a new approach to auditing in which companies must demonstrate to the regulator that they are ‘in control’. They must determine the relevance of a regulation for their business, justify which set of control measures they have taken to comply with it, and demonstrate that the control measures are operationally effective. In this paper we show how value-based argumentation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Substantive and procedural norms in normative multiagent systems.Guido Boella & Leendert van der Torre - 2008 - Journal of Applied Logic 6 (2):152-171.
  • I-ABM: combining institutional frameworks and agent-based modelling for the design of enforcement policies.Tina Balke, Marina De Vos & Julian Padget - 2013 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 21 (4):371-398.
    Computer science advocates institutional frameworks as an effective tool for modelling policies and reasoning about their interplay. In practice, the rules or policies, of which the institutional framework consists, are often specified using a formal language, which allows for the full verification and validation of the framework (e.g. the consistency of policies) and the interplay between the policies and actors (e.g. violations). However, when modelling large-scale realistic systems, with numerous decision-making entities, scalability and complexity issues arise making it possible only (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An executable specification of a formal argumentation protocol.Alexander Artikis, Marek Sergot & Jeremy Pitt - 2007 - Artificial Intelligence 171 (10-15):776-804.
  • Deontic logic.Paul McNamara - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Fundamental Legal Concepts: A Teleological Characterisation.Giovanni Sartor - forthcoming - Artificial Intelligence and Law.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ten philosophical problems in deontic logic.Gabriella Pigozzi, J. Hansen & Leon van der Torre - manuscript
    The paper discusses ten philosophical problems in deontic logic: how to formally represent norms, when a set of norms may be termed ‘coherent’, how to deal with normative conflicts, how contraryto-duty obligations can be appropriately modeled, how dyadic deontic operators may be redefined to relate to sets of norms instead of preference relations between possible worlds, how various concepts of permission can be accommodated, how meaning postulates and counts-as conditionals can be taken into account, and how sets of norms may (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hohfeld relations and spielraum for action.Lars Lindahl - 2006 - Análisis Filosófico 26 (2):325-355.
    The paper intends to show, that W. N. Hohfeld's theory of fundamental jural relations is relevant to economic theory, and that Hohfeld's system can be reconstructed by the concepts of 'liberty space' and 'ability space', understood as an agent's Spielraum for action. The first half of the paper is devoted to an exposition of Hohfeld's system and to the question of its relation to the economic analysis of property rights. The second half concerns Spielraum theory and the reformulation of Hohfeldian (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation