Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Connectionist learning and the challenge of real environments.Mark Weaver & Stephen Kaplan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):510-511.
  • Directions in Connectionist Research: Tractable Computations Without Syntactically Structured Representations.Jonathan Waskan & William Bechtel - 1997 - Metaphilosophy 28 (1‐2):31-62.
    Figure 1: A pr ototyp ical exa mple of a three-layer feed forward network, used by Plunkett and M archm an (1 991 ) to simulate learning the past-tense of En glish verbs. The inpu t units encode representations of the three phonemes of the present tense of the artificial words used in this simulation. Th e netwo rk is trained to produce a representation of the phonemes employed in the past tense form and the suffix (/d/, /ed/, or /t/) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hierarchical Incremental Class Learning with Output Parallelism.Sheng-Uei Guan & Kai Wang - 2007 - Journal of Intelligent Systems 16 (2):167-193.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is it like to be a patient with apperceptive agnosia?Shaun P. Vecera & Kendra S. Gilds - 1997 - Consciousness and Cognition 6 (2-3):237-66.
    Neuropsychological deficits have been widely used to elucidate normal cognitive functioning. Can patients with such deficits also be used to understand conscious visual experience? In this paper, we ask what it would be like to be a patient with apperceptive agnosia . Philosophical analyses of such questions have suggested that subjectively experiencing what another person experiences would be impossible. Although such roadblocks into the conscious experience of others exist, the experimental study of both patients and neurologically normal subjects can be (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Connectionist models learn what?Timothy van Gelder - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):509-510.
  • Advances in neural network theory.Gérard Toulouse - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):509-509.
  • Connectionist models: Too little too soon?William Timberlake - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):508-509.
  • Relational learning re-examined.Chris Thornton & Andy Clark - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1):83-83.
    We argue that existing learning algorithms are often poorly equipped to solve problems involving a certain type of important and widespread regularity that we call “type-2 regularity.” The solution in these cases is to trade achieved representation against computational search. We investigate several ways in which such a trade-off may be pursued including simple incremental learning, modular connectionism, and the developmental hypothesis of “representational redescription.”.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Problems of extension, representation, and computational irreducibility.Patrick Suppes - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):507-508.
  • There is more to learning then meeth the eye.Noel E. Sharkey - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):506-507.
  • Diversity and Unity of Modularity.Bongrae Seok - 2006 - Cognitive Science 30 (2):347-380.
    Since the publication of Fodor's (1983) The Modularity of Mind, there have been quite a few discussions of cognitive modularity among cognitive scientists. Generally, in those discussions, modularity means a property of specialized cognitive processes or a domain-specific body of information. In actuality, scholars understand modularity in many different ways. Different characterizations of modularity and modules were proposed and discussed, but they created misunderstanding and confusion. In this article, I classified and analyzed different approaches to modularity and argued for the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Statistical learning of tone sequences by human infants and adults.Jenny R. Saffran, Elizabeth K. Johnson, Richard N. Aslin & Elissa L. Newport - 1999 - Cognition 70 (1):27-52.
  • Do connectionist representations earn their explanatory keep?William Ramsey - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):34-66.
    In this paper I assess the explanatory role of internal representations in connectionist models of cognition. Focusing on both the internal‘hidden’units and the connection weights between units, I argue that the standard reasons for viewing these components as representations are inadequate to bestow an explanatorily useful notion of representation. Hence, nothing would be lost from connectionist accounts of cognitive processes if we were to stop viewing the weights and hidden units as internal representations.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Do Connectionist Representations Earn Their Explanatory Keep?William Ramsey - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):34-66.
    In this paper I assess the explanatory role of internal representations in connectionist models of cognition. Focusing on both the internal‘hidden’units and the connection weights between units, I argue that the standard reasons for viewing these components as representations are inadequate to bestow an explanatorily useful notion of representation. Hence, nothing would be lost from connectionist accounts of cognitive processes if we were to stop viewing the weights and hidden units as internal representations.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The analysis of the learning needs to be deeper.John E. Rager - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):505-506.
  • Is perception informationally encapsulated? The issue of the theory‐ladenness of perception.Athanassios Raftopoulos - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (3):423-451.
    Fodor has argued that observation is theory neutral, since the perceptual systems are modular, that is, they are domain‐specific, encapsulated, mandatory, fast, hard‐wired in the organism, and have a fixed neural architecture. Churchland attacks the theoretical neutrality of observation on the grounds that (a) the abundant top‐down pathways in the brain suggest the cognitive penetration of perception and (b) perceptual learning can change in the wiring of the perceptual systems. In this paper I introduce a distinction between sensation, perception, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Realistic neural nets need to learn iconic representations.W. A. Phillips, P. J. B. Hancock & L. S. Smith - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):505-505.
  • Learning from learned networks.M. Pavel - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):503-504.
  • Keeping representations at bay.Stanley Munsat - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):502-503.
  • On the Validity of Simulating Stagewise Development by Means of PDP Networks: Application of Catastrophe Analysis and an Experimental Test of Rule‐Like Network Performance.Risto Miikkulainen, Regina Vollmeyer, Bruce D. Burns, Keith J. Holyoak, Maartje E. J. Raijmakers, Sylvester van Koten, Peter C. M. Molenaar, Daniel Jurafsky, Gerhard Weber & Giuseppe Mantovani - 1996 - Cognitive Science 20 (1):101-136.
    This article addresses the ability of Parallel Distributed Processing (PDP) networks to generate stagewise cognitive development in accordance with Piaget's theory of cognitive epigenesis. We carried out a replication study of the simulation experiments by McClelland (1989) and McClelland and Jenkins (1991) in which a PDP network learns to solve balance scale problems. In objective tests motivated from catastrophe theory, a mathematical theory of transitions in epigenetical systems, no evidence for stage transitions in network performance was found. It is concluded (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Subsymbolic Case‐Role Analysis of Sentences with Embedded Clauses.Risto Miikkulainen - 1996 - Cognitive Science 20 (1):47-73.
    A distributed neural network model called SPEC for processing sentences with recursive relative clauses is described. The model is based on separating the tasks of segmenting the input word sequence into clauses, forming the case‐role representations, and keeping track of the recursive embeddings into different modules. The system needs to be trained only with the basic sentence constructs, and it generalizes not only to new instances of familiar relative clause structures but to novel structures as well. SPEC exhibits plausible memory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Can connectionism save constructivism?Gary F. Marcus - 1998 - Cognition 66 (2):153-182.
  • Can connectionism save constructivism?Gary F. Marcus - 1998 - Cognition 66 (2):153-182.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Cognitive architecture and descent with modification☆.G. Marcus - 2006 - Cognition 101 (2):443-465.
  • Toward a unification of conditioning and cognition in animal learning.William S. Maki - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):501-502.
  • On learnability, empirical foundations, and naturalness.W. J. M. Levelt - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):501-501.
  • Approaches to learning and representation.Pat Langley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):500-501.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What can psychologists learn from hidden-unit nets?K. Lamberts & G. D'Ydewalle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):499-500.
  • Learning non-local dependencies.Gustav Kuhn & Zoltán Dienes - 2008 - Cognition 106 (1):184-206.
  • How connectionist models learn: The course of learning in connectionist networks.John K. Kruschke - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):498-499.
  • Acquisition and extinction in autoshaping.Sham Kakade & Peter Dayan - 2002 - Psychological Review 109 (3):533-544.
  • A non-empiricist perspective on learning in layered networks.Michael I. Jordan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):497-498.
  • Encoding Shape and Spatial Relations: The Role of Receptive Field Size in Coordinating Complementary Representations.Robert A. Jacobs & Stephen M. Kosslyn - 1994 - Cognitive Science 18 (3):361-386.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The neural basis of human error processing: Reinforcement learning, dopamine, and the error-related negativity.Clay B. Holroyd & Michael G. H. Coles - 2002 - Psychological Review 109 (4):679-709.
  • But what is the substance of connectionist representation?James Hendler - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):496-497.
  • What connectionist models learn: Learning and representation in connectionist networks.Stephen José Hanson & David J. Burr - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):471-489.
    Connectionist models provide a promising alternative to the traditional computational approach that has for several decades dominated cognitive science and artificial intelligence, although the nature of connectionist models and their relation to symbol processing remains controversial. Connectionist models can be characterized by three general computational features: distinct layers of interconnected units, recursive rules for updating the strengths of the connections during learning, and “simple” homogeneous computing elements. Using just these three features one can construct surprisingly elegant and powerful models of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Learning and representation: Tensions at the interface.Steven José Hanson - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):511-518.
  • Expose hidden assumptions in network theory.Karl Haberlandt - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):495-496.
  • Domain-Creating Constraints.Robert L. Goldstone & David Landy - 2010 - Cognitive Science 34 (7):1357-1377.
    The contributions to this special issue on cognitive development collectively propose ways in which learning involves developing constraints that shape subsequent learning. A learning system must be constrained to learn efficiently, but some of these constraints are themselves learnable. To know how something will behave, a learner must know what kind of thing it is. Although this has led previous researchers to argue for domain-specific constraints that are tied to different kinds/domains, an exciting possibility is that kinds/domains themselves can be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Are connectionist models just statistical pattern classifiers?Richard M. Golden - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):494-495.
  • Trading spaces: Computation, representation, and the limits of uninformed learning.Andy Clark & Chris Thornton - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1):57-66.
    Some regularities enjoy only an attenuated existence in a body of training data. These are regularities whose statistical visibility depends on some systematic recoding of the data. The space of possible recodings is, however, infinitely large – it is the space of applicable Turing machines. As a result, mappings that pivot on such attenuated regularities cannot, in general, be found by brute-force search. The class of problems that present such mappings we call the class of “type-2 problems.” Type-1 problems, by (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Symbolically speaking: a connectionist model of sentence production.Franklin Chang - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (5):609-651.
    The ability to combine words into novel sentences has been used to argue that humans have symbolic language production abilities. Critiques of connectionist models of language often center on the inability of these models to generalize symbolically (Fodor & Pylyshyn, 1988; Marcus, 1998). To address these issues, a connectionist model of sentence production was developed. The model had variables (role‐concept bindings) that were inspired by spatial representations (Landau & Jackendoff, 1993). In order to take advantage of these variables, a novel (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Connectionism and classical computation.Nick Chater - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):493-494.
  • Understanding the Emergence of Modularity in Neural Systems.John A. Bullinaria - 2007 - Cognitive Science 31 (4):673-695.
    Modularity in the human brain remains a controversial issue, with disagreement over the nature of the modules that exist, and why, when, and how they emerge. It is a natural assumption that modularity offers some form of computational advantage, and hence evolution by natural selection has translated those advantages into the kind of modular neural structures familiar to cognitive scientists. However, simulations of the evolution of simplified neural systems have shown that, in many cases, it is actually non-modular architectures that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Representational systems and symbolic systems.Gordon D. A. Brown & Mike Oaksford - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):492-493.
  • What connectionists learn: Comparisons of model and neural nets.Bruce Bridgeman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):491-492.
  • VAMP (Voting Agent Model of Preferences): A computational model of individual multi-attribute choice.Anouk S. Bergner, Daniel M. Oppenheimer & Greg Detre - 2019 - Cognition 192 (C):103971.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Levels of description and explanation in cognitive science.William Bechtel - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (1):1-25.
    The notion of levels has been widely used in discussions of cognitive science, especially in discussions of the relation of connectionism to symbolic modeling of cognition. I argue that many of the notions of levels employed are problematic for this purpose, and develop an alternative notion grounded in the framework of mechanistic explanation. By considering the source of the analogies underlying both symbolic modeling and connectionist modeling, I argue that neither is likely to provide an adequate analysis of processes at (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Multiple Realizability Revisited: Linking Cognitive and Neural States.William Bechtel - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (2):175-207.
    The claim of the multiple realizability of mental states by brain states has been a major feature of the dominant philosophy of mind of the late 20th century. The claim is usually motivated by evidence that mental states are multiply realized, both within humans and between humans and other species. We challenge this contention by focusing on how neuroscientists differentiate brain areas. The fact that they rely centrally on psychological measures in mapping the brain and do so in a comparative (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   196 citations  
  • Currents in connectionism.William Bechtel - 1993 - Minds and Machines 3 (2):125-153.
    This paper reviews four significant advances on the feedforward architecture that has dominated discussions of connectionism. The first involves introducing modularity into networks by employing procedures whereby different networks learn to perform different components of a task, and a Gating Network determines which network is best equiped to respond to a given input. The second consists in the use of recurrent inputs whereby information from a previous cycle of processing is made available on later cycles. The third development involves developing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations