Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A brief history of negation.J. L. Speranza & Laurence R. Horn - 2010 - Journal of Applied Logic 8 (3):277-301.
  • On human needs and moral appraisals.Kai Nielsen - 1963 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 6 (1-4):170 – 183.
    For a large and important range of cases the connection between ?X needs y? and ?X ought to have y?, though not an entailment, is still non?contingent. Sentences in which ?needs? occurs have several uses) one of which is normative; when such sentences are used to make statements, the statements constitute a good reason for asserting that what is needed ought to be done. It must, however, be recognized that such a reason may not be a sufficient reason for the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scepticism and absurdity.Ingemund Gullvåg - 1964 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 7 (1-4):163-190.
    Analytic rejections of extreme traditional views, especially scepticism, as ?absurd? in some sense of violating ?rules? of discourse, arc considered. References to linguistic and pragmatic rules are discussed and found inadequate as bases for rejecting scepticism. References to logical principles alone are found to lead into scepticism. The claim that epistemology and scepticism take for granted an inadequate theory of words like ?know?, or ?knowledge?, as descriptive predicates, is considered. Alternatives, construing such words as appraisive or performative, are discussed, but (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zur Methodologie von Kombinationstests in der analytischen Philosophie.Hans-Ulrich Hoche - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):28-54.
    Summary Ordinary language philosophers frequently draw on the fact that an appropriately selected sentential combination of the form p but not q can, or cannot, be uttered without absurdity; however, they do so without sufficient reflection on the methodology of such combination tests, which results in considerable shortcomings even in practical application. To improve things, I shall discuss two criteria for distinguishing ‘pragmatic’ from ‘non-pragmatic’ implications and for separating the latter into ‘linguistic’ (‘semantic’ and ‘syntactical’) and ‘non-linguistic’ ones (2–3); consider (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Do illocutionary, or neustic, negations exist?Hans-Ulrich Hoche - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (1):127 - 136.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Epistemic logic and the methods of philosophical analysis.Jaakko Hintikka - 1968 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 46 (1):37 – 51.
  • The logic of assertion.Ingemund Gullvåg - 1978 - Theoria 44 (2):75-116.
    The aim is to fashion intuitive conditions of pragmatic consistency for the speech act of assertion into a formal theory, so as to exclude "pragmatically absurd" utterances (contradictory statements, versions of the liar, moore's paradox, etc.). a core theory i for a concept of pragmatic implication (tentatively identified with overt or covert assertion) and an added theory ib for implied belief are constructed on the pattern of a weak modal system, whose specific axiom is taken to explicate what it means (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An emendation of R. G. Collingwood's doctrine of absolute presuppositions.Kenneth Laine Ketner - 1973 - [Lubbock,: Texas Tech Press].
  • Implicature.Wayne Davis - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Experimental Philosophy: 1935-1965.Taylor Murphy - 2014 - In Tania Lombrozo, Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Volume 1. Oxford University Press. pp. vol. 1, pp. 325-368.
    In the heyday of linguistic philosophy an experimental philosophy movement was born, and this chapter tells its story, both in its historical and philosophical context and as it is connected to controversies about experimental philosophy today. From its humble beginnings at the Vienna Circle, the movement matured into a vibrant research program at Oslo, and sought adventure at Berkeley thereafter. The harsh and uncharitable reaction it met is surprising but understandable in light of disciplinary tensions and the legacy of antipsychologism—sentiments (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Saying, meaning, and implicating.Kent Bach - 2012 - In Keith Allan & Kasia Jaszczolt (eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press.