Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The African Philosophy Reader: a text with readings.P. H. Coetzee & A. P. J. Roux (eds.) - 1998 - London: Routledge.
    Divided into eight sections, each with introductory essays, the selections offer rich and detailed insights into a diverse multinational philosophical landscape. Revealed in this pathbreaking work is the way in which traditional philosophical issues related to ethics, metaphysics, and epistemology, for instance, take on specific forms in Africa's postcolonial struggles. Much of its moral, political, and social philosophy is concerned with the turbulent processes of embracing modern identities while protecting ancient cultures.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Les conditions de l'interprétation.Martin Montminy - 1996 - Dialogue 35 (3):505-528.
    Donald Davidson considère qu'une théorie de l'interprétation doit êtreradicale, c'est-à-dire qu'elle ne doit présupposer aucune connaissance de la langue à interpréter. Cette exigence repose sur l'idée suivante: si une théorie de l'interprétation pour une langue L présuppose une certaine compréhension de L, alors elle perd son pouvoir explicatif et échoue à rendre compte de ce qui permet la compréhension de L. L'interpr'tation radicale a l'avantage de nous forcer à rendre explicite ce qui est à l'œuvre dans le processus d'interprétation du (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deconstruction, postmodernism and philosophy of science: Some Epistemo‐critical bearings.Christopher Norris - 1998 - Cultural Values 2 (1):18-50.
    This essay argues a case for viewing Derrida's work in the context of recent French epistemology and philosophy of science; more specifically, the critical‐rationalist approach exemplified by thinkers such as Bachelard and Canguilhem. I trace this line of descent principally through Derrida's essay ‘White Mythology: Metaphor in the Text of Philosophy’. My conclusions are (1) that we get Derrida wrong if we read him as a fargone antirealist for whom there is nothing ‘outside the text'; (2) that he provides some (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Relativism due to underdetermination of theory by data.Saeid Zibakalam - 1994 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8 (3):211 – 228.
  • Thinking in multitudes: Questionnaires and composite cases in early American psychology.Jacy L. Young - 2020 - History of the Human Sciences 33 (3-4):160-174.
    In the late 19th century, the questionnaire was one means of taking the case study into the multitudes. This article engages with Forrester’s idea of thinking in cases as a means of interrogating questionnaire-based research in early American psychology. Questionnaire research was explicitly framed by psychologists as a practice involving both natural historical and statistical forms of scientific reasoning. At the same time, questionnaire projects failed to successfully enact the latter aspiration in terms of synthesizing masses of collected data into (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Relatively Speaking: The Coherence of Anti-Realist Relativism.James O. Young - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):503 - 509.
    The current debate between realists and anti-realists has brought to the fore some ancient questions about the coherence of relativism. Realism is the doctrine according to which the truth of sentences is determined by the way things really are. Truth is thus the result of a relation between sentences and reality. One species of anti-realism holds, on the contrary, the truth results from a relation between sentences within a theory: a sentence is true if warranted by a correct theory.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Presuppositional Languages and the Failure of Cross-Language Understanding.Xinli Wang - 2003 - Dialogue 42 (1):53-77.
    Why is mutual understanding between two substantially different comprehensive language communities often problematic and even unattainable? To answer this question, the author first introduces a notion of presuppositional languages. Based on the semantic structure of a presuppositional language, the author identifies a significant condition necessary for effective understanding of a language: the interpreter is able to effectively understand a language only if he/she is able to recognize and comprehend its metaphysical presuppositions. The essential role of the knowledge of metaphysical presuppositions (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What Makes Human Differences into Cultural Differences.Harry van den Bouwhuijsen - 1995 - Philosophica 55.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Great (Scientific) Divergence: Synergies and Fault Lines in Global Histories of Science.Helen Tilley - 2019 - Isis 110 (1):129-136.
    Historians of science have a lingering Europe (and U.S.) problem, even as the field has undergone its own transnational, imperial, and global turns that have broadened its scope. Likewise, area studies scholars have a lingering science problem, in spite of the growing chorus of voices insisting that non-European peoples’ knowledge and innovations warrant a place in global histories about science, technology, and medicine. This essay examines these two fault lines using the biochemist-turned-historian Joseph Needham as a point of departure. Needham’s (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representation and the realist-constructivist controversy.Paul Tibbetts - 1988 - Human Studies 11 (2-3):117 - 132.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Idea of Philosophy and Its Relation to Social Science.Mark Theunissen - 2014 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44 (2):151-178.
    This article takes up Winch’s exploration of a certain dialectic in philosophical accounts of social inquiry, the poles of which I refer to as the under-laborer and over-laborer conceptions of philosophy. I argue that these conceptions, shown in Risjord and Reed, respectively, are caught in a dialectic of treating philosophy’s roles as either modestly clarifying or broadly determining the claims of social science. A third conception of philosophy, the therapeutic conception, is exemplified by Read et al.’s “New Wittgensteinian” interpretation of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Case for A Feminist Philosophy of Religion: Transforming Philosophy's Imagery and Myths.Pamela Sue Anderson - 2001 - Ars Disputandi 1:1-17.
  • Understanding alien morals.Gopal Sreenivasan - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (1):1-32.
    Anthropologists often claim to have understood an ethical outlook that they nevertheless believe is largely false. Some moral philosophers---e.g., Susan Hurley---argue that this claim is incoherent because understanding an ethical outlook necessarily involves believing it to be largely true. To reach this conclusion, they apply an argument of Donald Davidson’s to the ethical case. My central aim is to defend the coherence of the anthropologists’ claim against this argument.To begin with, I specify a candidate-language that contains a significant number of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The implicit epistemology of White Fragility.Alan Sokal - 2023 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 57 (2):517-552.
    I extract, and then analyse critically, the epistemological ideas that are implicit in Robin DiAngelo's best-selling book White Fragility and her other writings. On what grounds, according to DiAngelo, can people know what they claim to know? And on what grounds does DiAngelo know what she claims to know?
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relativism, Incoherence, and the Strong Programme.Harvey Siegel - 2011 - In Richard Schantz & Markus Seidel (eds.), The Problem of Relativism in the Sociology of (Scientific) Knowledge. ontos. pp. 41-64.
  • Magic witchcraft and the materialist mentality.W. W. Sharrock & R. J. Anderson - 1985 - Human Studies 8 (4):357 - 375.
  • Human universals and understanding a different socioculture.Theodore R. Schatzki - 2003 - Human Studies 26 (1):11-20.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Gellner, science and globalization.Ralph Schroeder - 2015 - Thesis Eleven 128 (1):10-25.
    Cognition, or scientific knowledge, is the fulcrum of Gellner’s philosophy of history. Science, for Gellner, is central to understanding the rise of the West and also to his defence of Enlightenment rationality against postmodernism and other forms of relativism. This way of thinking has recently been challenged, first, by global historians who locate the ‘great divergence’ in the 19th century rather than earlier, and second, by those who assign to the Enlightenment a pernicious role and argue that rationality and scientific (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Disinterring Basic Color Terms : a study in the mystique of cognitivism.Barbara Saunders - 1995 - History of the Human Sciences 8 (4):19-38.
  • The cross-cultural study of mind and behaviour: a word of caution.Carles Salazar - 2022 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology (2):1-18.
    Nobody doubts that culture plays a decisive role in understanding human forms of life. But it is unclear how this decisive role should be integrated into a comprehensive explanatory model of human behaviour that brings together naturalistic and social-scientific perspectives. Cultural difference, cultural learning, cultural determination do not mix well with the factors that are normally given full explanatory value in the more naturalistic approaches to the study of human behaviour. My purpose in this paper is to alert to some (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Narrative in African Philosophy.Richard H. Bell - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (249):363 - 379.
  • Justifying Sociological Knowledge: From Realism to Interpretation.Isaac Reed - 2008 - Sociological Theory 26 (2):101-129.
    In the context of calls for "postpositivist" sociology, realism has emerged as a powerful and compelling epistemology for social science. In transferring and transforming scientific realism --a philosophy of natural science--into a justificatory discourse for social science, realism splits into two parts: a strict, highly naturalistic realism and a reflexive, more mediated, and critical realism. Both forms of realism, however, suffer from conceptual ambiguities, omissions, and elisions that make them an inappropriate epistemology for social science. Examination of these problems in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The epistemology of democracy: The epistemic virtues of democracy.Snjezana Prijic-Samarzija - 2020 - Filozofija I Društvo 31 (1):56-70.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Making Aliens: Problems of Description in Science Fiction and Social Science.David Oldman - 1983 - Theory, Culture and Society 2 (1):49-65.
  • Ontological relativity and meaning‐variance: A critical‐constructive review.Christopher Norris - 1997 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 40 (2):139 – 173.
    This article offers a critical review of various ontological-relativist arguments, mostly deriving from the work of W. V. Quine and Thomas K hn. I maintain that these arguments are (1) internally contradictory, (2) incapable of accounting for our knowledge of the growth of scientific knowledge, and (3) shown up as fallacious from the standpoint of a causal-realist approach to issues of truth, meaning, and interpretation. Moreover, they have often been viewed as lending support to such programmes as the 'strong' sociology (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Relativism and truth: A misguided polarity.Maurizio Passerin D'Entrèves - 1995 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 21 (1):17-35.
  • Women, ethics, and MBAs.Cheryl MacLellan & John Dobson - 1997 - Journal of Business Ethics 16 (11):1201-1209.
    We argue that the declining female enrollment in graduate business schools is a manifestation of gender bias in business education. The extant conceptual foundation of business education is one which views business activity in terms of a game with fixed and wholly material objectives. This concept betrays an underlying value system that reflects a male orientation. Business education is not merely amoral, therefore, but is gender biased. We suggest that business educators adopt a broadened behavioral rubric. Virtue-ethics theory provides such (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Social Constructivism in Science and Technology Studies.Michael Lynch - 2016 - Human Studies 39 (1):101-112.
    Berger and Luckmann’s concept of “social construction” has been widely adopted in many fields of the humanities and social sciences in the half-century since they wrote The Social Construction of Reality. One field in which constructivism was especially provocative was in Science and Technology Studies, where it was expanded beyond the social domain to encompass the practices and contents of contemporary natural science. This essay discusses the relationship between social construction in STS and Berger and Luckmann’s original conception of it, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Epistemic relativism.Steven Luper - 2004 - Philosophical Issues 14 (1):271–295.
    Epistemic relativism rejects the idea that claims can be assessed from a universally applicable, objective standpoint. It is greatly disdained because it suggests that the real ‘basis’ for our views is something fleeting, such as ‘‘the techniques of mass persuasion’’ (Thomas Kuhn 1970) or the determination of intellectuals to achieve ‘‘solidarity’’ (Rorty 1984) or ‘‘keep the conversation going’’ (Rorty 1979). But epistemic relativism, like skepticism, is far easier to despise than to convincingly refute, for two main reasons. First, its definition (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Charité, traduction radicale et prélogicité.Sandra Laugier - 2001 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 1 (1):63-83.
    L’A. présente la pertinence anthropologique de la thèse d’indétermination de la traduction de Quine, en suggérant qu’elle joue contre le relativisme, mais aussi contre une certaine forme d’universalisme : c’est ce que montre une analyse de la notion de prélogicité, critiquée par Quine qui invente à cette occasion le « principe de charité ». L’examen des usages et de la portée d’un tel principe, et sa confrontation aux thèses de Lévy-Bruhl, permet, au-delà de Quine, de repenser l’invocation devenue trop courante (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Knowledge, Society, and History.Philip Kitcher - 1993 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):155 - 177.
    Here is a traditional way of thinking about human knowledge. Knowledge is a species of true belief. The crucial difference between knowledge and other kinds of true belief is that propositions that are known have a special property. Justified propositions either have intrinsic justification or else they are obtainable by means of a justification-conferring argument from other justified propositions that the knower believes. The only propositions with intrinsic justification are those that fall into one of two classes: the set of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The rationality of belief and other propositional attitudes.Thomas Kelly - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 110 (2):163-96.
    In this paper, I explore the question of whether the expected consequences of holding a belief can affect the rationality of doing so. Special attention is given to various ways in which one might attempt to exert some measure of control over what one believes and the normative status of the beliefs that result from the successful execution of such projects. I argue that the lessons which emerge from thinking about the case ofbelief have important implications for the way we (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Rational common ground in the sociology of knowledge.Jonathan Katz - 1989 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 19 (3):257-271.
  • Making noises in counterpoint or chorus: Putnam's rejection of relativism. [REVIEW]JefferyL Johnson - 1991 - Erkenntnis 34 (3):323--45.
    Putnam's internal realism entails the simultaneous rejection of metaphysical realism and (anything goes or total or cultural) relativism. Putnam argues, in some places, that relativism is self-contradictory, and in others, that it is self-refuting. This paper attempts the exegetical task of explicating these challenging arguments, and the critical task of suggesting that a full-blown epistemological relativism may be capable of surviving the Putnam attack.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Buddha as Pram? $$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{n}$$ abh?ta: Epithets and arguments in the Buddhist ?logical? tradition. [REVIEW]RogerR Jackson - 1988 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 16 (4):335-365.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Agency and Sovereignty: Georges Bataille's Anti-Humanist Conception of Child.Sharon Hunter - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (5):1186-1200.
    Georges Bataille (1887–1962) is one of the most significant thinkers of the 20th century, whose anti-humanist anthropology influenced subsequent existentialist and post-structuralist philosophy. His wide-ranging writings (across philosophy, archaeology, economics, sociology, poetry, erotica and history of art) frequently mention children, childhood and childishness, and yet there has hitherto been little to no attention paid to this aspect of his work. This article opens up a neglected theme in Bataille studies, and also explores the consequences of Bataille's presentation of the human (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Relativism or Anti-Anti-Relativism? Epistemological and Rhetorical Moves in Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science.Kathrin Hönig - 2005 - European Journal of Women's Studies 12 (4):407-419.
    Feminist approaches in epistemology and philosophy of science have frequently been labelled as ’relativist’, both by feminist as well as by non-feminist philosophers. Regularly the so labelled distance themselves from even the mere suspicion of relativist tendencies. There is a remarkable discrepancy between an attributed and a self-declared relativism. Taking the self-declared relativism of Lorraine Code as an example, the article argues that it is a case of a rhetorical not epistemological relativism, better termed as anti-anti-relativism, but that there are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Die Notwendigkeit globaler Philosophie.Stefan Gosepath - 2020 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 68 (6):943-956.
    When ‘we’ in the West talk about philosophy, we most often mean ‘Western Philosophy’, i. e. philosophy with ancient roots in Greece from the pre-Socratic period onwards until today, thereby neglecting other cultures and traditions, whose history of philosophical thinking is at least as old and important. This neglect of other philosophical traditions is a problem in general, since it is unfair, hegemonic, ignorant, and imprudent. The article argues that there are instrumental as well as intrinsic reasons to diversify and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Cultural Pluralism Relevant to Moral Knowledge?Alan Gewirth - 1994 - Social Philosophy and Policy 11 (1):22-43.
    Cultural pluralism is both a fact and a norm. It is a fact that our world, and indeed our society, are marked by a large diversity of cultures delineated in terms of race, class, gender, ethnicity, religion, ideology, and other partly interpenetrating variables. This fact raises the normative question of whether, or to what extent, such diversities should be recognized or even encouraged in policies concerning government, law, education, employment, the family, immigration, and other important areas of social concern.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Thomas Kuhn et l’oubli de la pratique.Roberto Frega - 2013 - Dialogue 52 (3):421-448.
    I examine Thomas Kuhn’s work regarding the role played by the concept of practice in the development of his theory of scientific rationality. I outline the epistemological implications of his theory of incommensurability. I then show how the original intuition of a practice-based and social conception of incommensurability is replaced by a more conventional linguistic interpretation. I then examine Kuhn’s solution to the problem of incommensurability and explain its inadequacy. I then show that, ultimately, his failure to grasp the epistemological (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rationality Assumptions and their Limits.Robert Feleppa - 2021 - Sage Publications Inc: Philosophy of the Social Sciences 51 (6):574-599.
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Volume 51, Issue 6, Page 574-599, December 2021. In “Different Cultures, Different Rationalities” Stephen Lukes weighs in on the controversies concerning the killing of Captain Cook by Hawaiians and what it says about the role of rationality assumptions in translation. While at first seeming to adopt a Davidsonian anti-relativist position concerning the enabling role of assumptions of common rationality in interpretation, Lukes rejects Davidson’s view, and opts instead for a “totalizing” strategy inspired by Mauss. Here (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward the Feminine Firm.John Dobson & Judith White - 1995 - Business Ethics Quarterly 5 (3):463-478.
    This paper concerns the influence of gender on a firm’s moral and economic performance. It supports Thomas White’s intimation of a male gender bias in the value system underlying extant business theory. We suggest that this gender bias may be corrected by drawing on the concept of substantive rationality inherent in virtue-ethics theory. This feminine-oriented relationship-based value system complements the essential nature of the firm as a nexus of relationships between stakeholders. Not only is this feminine firm morally desirable, but (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • For reflexivity as an epistemic criterion of ontological coherence and virtuous social theorizing.Christoforos Bouzanis - 2017 - History of the Human Sciences 30 (5):125-146.
    This article offers an approach that combines, on the one hand, the philosophical notion of reflexivity, which is related to the ideas of self-reference and paradox, and, on the other hand, the sociological discussion of epistemic reflexivity as a problem of coherence, which was mainly initiated by certain branches of ethnomethodology and social constructionism. This combinatory approach argues for reflexivity as an epistemic criterion of ontological coherence, which suggests that social ontologies should account for the possibility of self-reflective subjectivity – (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • La logique sauvage de Quine à Lévi-Strauss.Denis Bonnay & Sandra Laugier - 2003 - Archives de Philosophie 66 (1):49-72.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Critical comments on Pearce, african philosophy, and the sociological thesis.John A. I. Bewaji - 1995 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 25 (1):99-119.
    Pearce's "African Philosophy and the Sociological Thesis" makes very interesting reading. Why it is interesting is not because it advances the frontiers of philosophical discourse in Africa or globally but because it shows that certain unwarranted dispositions die hard and that deliberate ignorance, if that is what is displayed, is hard to cure. In this article the author comments on the following contentions made by Pearce: (1) philosophy has no social relevance and/or responsibility; (2) philosophy is purely a linguistic activity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Belief, apparitions, and rationality: The social scientific study of religion after Wittgenstein. [REVIEW]Edward Berryman - 2005 - Human Studies 28 (1):15 - 39.
    The goal I pursue is to redefine the study of religious epistemology on the basis of an ethnomethodological extension of Wittgenstein. This approach shows that the nature of religious belief and its relation to facts, proofs, and empirical reality are matters that are dealt with by ordinary members of society. The examination of this lay epistemology reveals that – far from being a settled and established entity – religious belief is a polymorphous phenomenon. Religious belief is a pragmatic resource whose (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Belief, Apparitions, and Rationality: The Social Scientific Study of Religion after Wittgenstein1.Edward Berryman - 2005 - Human Studies 28 (1):15-39.
    The goal I pursue is to redefine the study of religious epistemology on the basis of an ethnomethodological extension of Wittgenstein. This approach shows that the nature of religious belief and its relation to facts, proofs, and empirical reality are matters that are dealt with by ordinary members of society. The examination of this lay epistemology reveals that -- far from being a settled and established entity -- religious belief is a polymorphous phenomenon. Religious belief is a pragmatic resource whose (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Narrative in African Philosophy: Richard H. Bell.Richard H. Bell - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (249):363-379.
    P. O. Bodunrin, in his 1981 essay, asks: ‘Is there an African Philosophy, and if there is, what is it?’ This question has occupied centre stage among younger African intellectuals for about a decade now. The most articulate among these intellectuals, who are themselves philosophers, are Bodunrin , Kwasi Wiredu , H. Odera Oruka , Marcien Towa and Eboussi Boulaga , and Paulin Hountondji . These philosophers among others are in dialogue with one another and currently are seen to be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Normal or Abnormal? ‘Normative Uncertainty’ in Psychiatric Practice.Andrew M. Bassett & Charley Baker - 2015 - Journal of Medical Humanities 36 (2):89-111.
    The ‘multicultural clinical interaction’ presents itself as a dilemma for the mental health practitioner. Literature describes two problematic areas where this issues emerges - how to make an adequate distinction between religious rituals and the rituals that may be symptomatic of ‘obsessive compulsive disorder’ (OCD), and how to differentiate ‘normative’ religious or spiritual beliefs, behaviours, and experiences from ‘psychotic’ illnesses. When it comes to understanding service user’s ‘idioms of distress’, beliefs about how culture influences behaviour can create considerable confusion and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is there such a thing as a language?Dorit Bar-On & Mark Risjord - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (2):163-190.
    ‘There is no such thing as a language,’ Donald Davidson tells us. Though this is a startling claim in its own right, it seems especially puzzling coming from a leading theorizer about language. Over the years, Davidson’s important essays have sparked the hope that there is a route to a positive, nonskeptical theory of meaning for natural languages. This hope would seem to be dashed if there are no natural languages. Unless Davidson’s radical claim is a departure from his developed (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations