Switch to: References

Citations of:

Aspects of inductive logic

Amsterdam,: North Holland Pub. Co.. Edited by Patrick Suppes (1967)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Vagueness and Inductive Molding.J. R. Welch - 2007 - Synthese 154 (1):147-172.
    Vagueness is epistemic, according to some. Vagueness is ontological, according to others. This article deploys what I take to be a compromise position. Predicates are coined in specific contexts for specific purposes, but these limited practices do not automatically fix the extensions of predicates over the domain of all objects. The linguistic community using the predicate has rarely considered, much less decided, all questions that might arise about the predicate’s extension. To this extent, the ontological view is correct. But a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Decision theory and cognitive choice.John R. Welch - 2011 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (2):147-172.
    The focus of this study is cognitive choice: the selection of one cognitive option (a hypothesis, a theory, or an axiom, for instance) rather than another. The study proposes that cognitive choice should be based on the plausibilities of states posited by rival cognitive options and the utilities of these options' information outcomes. The proposal introduces a form of decision theory that is novel because comparative; it permits many choices among cognitive options to be based on merely comparative plausibilities and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inductive logic with causal modalities: A deterministic approach.Soshichi Uchii - 1973 - Synthese 26 (2):264 - 303.
  • Inductive explanation.Raimo Tuomela - 1981 - Synthese 48 (2):257 - 294.
  • Probability logic and combining evidence.Theodore Hailperin - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (3):249-269.
    In Hailperin 1996 , in addition to its formal development of Probability Logic, there are many sections devoted to historical origins, illustrative examples, and discussion of related work by other authors. Here selected portions of its formal treatment are summarized and then used as a basis for a probability logic treatment of combining evidence.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Coherence, striking agreement, and reliability: On a putative vindication of the Shogenji measure.Michael Schippers - 2014 - Synthese 191 (15):3661-3684.
    Striving for a probabilistic explication of coherence, scholars proposed a distinction between agreement and striking agreement. In this paper I argue that only the former should be considered a genuine concept of coherence. In a second step the relation between coherence and reliability is assessed. I show that it is possible to concur with common intuitions regarding the impact of coherence on reliability in various types of witness scenarios by means of an agreement measure of coherence. Highlighting the need to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reasoning defeasibly about probabilities.John L. Pollock - 2011 - Synthese 181 (2):317-352.
    In concrete applications of probability, statistical investigation gives us knowledge of some probabilities, but we generally want to know many others that are not directly revealed by our data. For instance, we may know prob(P/Q) (the probability of P given Q) and prob(P/R), but what we really want is prob(P/Q& R), and we may not have the data required to assess that directly. The probability calculus is of no help here. Given prob(P/Q) and prob(P/R), it is consistent with the probability (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Review. [REVIEW]Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1973 - Synthese 25 (3-4):417-436.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A rule of acceptance based on logical probability.Halina Mortimer - 1973 - Synthese 26 (2):259 - 263.
  • Ambiguity, inductive systems, and the modeling of subjective probability judgements.Giovanni B. Moneta - 1991 - Philosophical Psychology 4 (2):267 – 285.
    Gambles which induce the decision-maker to experience ambiguity about the relative likelihood of events often give rise to ambiguity-seeking and ambiguity-avoidance, which imply violation of additivity and Savage's axioms. The inability of the subjective Bayesian theory to account for these empirical regularities has determined a dichotomy between normative and descriptive views of subjective probability. This paper proposes a framework within which the two perspectives can be reconciled. First, a formal definition of ambiguity is given over a continuum ranging from ignorance (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Predictive Probability and Analogy by Similarity in Inductive Logic.Maria Concetta Di Maio - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (3):369 - 394.
    The λ-continuum of inductive methods was derived from an assumption, called λ-condition, which says that the probability of finding an individual having property $x_{j}$ depends only on the number of observed individuals having property $x_{j}$ and on the total number of observed individuals. So, according to that assumption, all individuals with properties which are different from $x_{j}$ have equal weight with respect to that probability and, in particular, it does not matter whether any individual was observed having some property similar (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Probabilistic pettifoggery.Isaac Levi - 1986 - Erkenntnis 25 (2):133 - 140.
  • Probability logic, logical probability, and inductive support.Isaac Levi - 2010 - Synthese 172 (1):97-118.
    This paper seeks to defend the following conclusions: The program advanced by Carnap and other necessarians for probability logic has little to recommend it except for one important point. Credal probability judgments ought to be adapted to changes in evidence or states of full belief in a principled manner in conformity with the inquirer’s confirmational commitments—except when the inquirer has good reason to modify his or her confirmational commitment. Probability logic ought to spell out the constraints on rationally coherent confirmational (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Information and inference.Isaac Levi - 1967 - Synthese 17 (1):369 - 391.
  • Rationality as weighted averaging.Keith Lehrer - 1983 - Synthese 57 (3):283 - 295.
    Weighted averaging is a method for aggregating the totality of information, both regimented and unregimented, possessed by an individual or group of individuals. The application of such a method may be warranted by a theorem of the calculus of probability, simple conditionalization, or Jeffrey's formula for probability kinematics, all of which average in terms of the prior probability of evidence statements. Weighted averaging may, however, be applied as a method of rational aggregation of the probabilities of diverse perspectives or persons (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Tyche and Athena.Henry E. Kyburg - 1979 - Synthese 40 (3):415 - 438.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the generalization of the continuum of inductive methods to universal hypotheses.Theo A. F. Kuipers - 1978 - Synthese 37 (3):255 - 284.
  • Hempel’s logic of confirmation.Franz Huber - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 139 (2):181-189.
    This paper presents a new analysis of C.G. Hempel’s conditions of adequacy for any relation of confirmation [Hempel C. G. (1945). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press, pp. 3–51.], differing from the one Carnap gave in §87 of his [1962. Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.]. Hempel, it is argued, felt the need for two concepts of confirmation: one aiming at true hypotheses and another (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Assessing theories, Bayes style.Franz Huber - 2008 - Synthese 161 (1):89-118.
    The problem addressed in this paper is “the main epistemic problem concerning science”, viz. “the explication of how we compare and evaluate theories [...] in the light of the available evidence” (van Fraassen, BC, 1983, Theory comparison and relevant Evidence. In J. Earman (Ed.), Testing scientific theories (pp. 27–42). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press). Sections 1– 3 contain the general plausibility-informativeness theory of theory assessment. In a nutshell, the message is (1) that there are two values a theory should exhibit: (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Carnap's inductive probabilities as a contribution to decision theory.Joachim Hornung - 1980 - Metamedicine 1 (3):325-367.
  • Carnap's inductive probabilities as a contribution to decision theory.Joachim Hornung - 1980 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 1 (3):325-367.
    Common probability theories only allow the deduction of probabilities by using previously known or presupposed probabilities. They do not, however, allow the derivation of probabilities from observed data alone. The question thus arises as to how probabilities in the empirical sciences, especially in medicine, may be arrived at. Carnap hoped to be able to answer this question byhis theory of inductive probabilities. In the first four sections of the present paper the above mentioned problem is discussed in general. After a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Non-zero probabilities for universal generalizations.Ruurik Holm - 2013 - Synthese 190 (18):4001-4007.
    This article discusses the classical problem of zero probability of universal generalizations in Rudolf Carnap’s inductive logic. A correction rule for updating the inductive method on the basis of evidence will be presented. It will be shown that this rule has the effect that infinite streams of uniform evidence assume a non-zero limit probability. Since Carnap’s inductive logic is based on finite domains of individuals, the probability of the corresponding universal quantification changes accordingly. This implies that universal generalizations can receive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Statistics, induction, and lawlikeness: Comments on dr. Vetter's paper.Jaakko Hintikka - 1969 - Synthese 20 (1):72 - 83.
  • Philosophy of science (wissenschaftstheorie) in finland.Jaakko Hintikka - 1970 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 1 (1):119-132.
    Summary A survey of recent work in the philosophy of science in Finland, with a bibliography. The main sources of influence emphasized are Eino Kaila (1890–1958) and G. H. von Wright (b. 1916). The main topics covered are: induction and probability; information and explanation; the acceptance and application of theories; the role of auxiliary (theoretical) terms; measurement; general methodology of social and behavioral sciences; finalistic explanation; methodology of sociology and history.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Carnap's new system of inductive logic.Risto Hilpinen - 1973 - Synthese 25 (3-4):307 - 333.
  • The structure of logical probabilities.Jens Erik Fenstad - 1968 - Synthese 18 (1):1 - 23.
  • Bayesianism and the rationality of scientific inference. [REVIEW]Jon Dorling - 1972 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (2):181-190.
  • The role of ambiguity in manipulating voter behavior.Raymond Dacey - 1979 - Theory and Decision 10 (1-4):265-279.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An interrogative account of the dialectical inquiring system based upon the economic theory of information.Raymond Dacey - 1981 - Synthese 47 (1):43 - 55.
  • Generalized logical consequence: Making room for induction in the logic of science. [REVIEW]Samir Chopra & Eric Martin - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (3):245-280.
    We present a framework that provides a logic for science by generalizing the notion of logical (Tarskian) consequence. This framework will introduce hierarchies of logical consequences, the first level of each of which is identified with deduction. We argue for identification of the second level of the hierarchies with inductive inference. The notion of induction presented here has some resonance with Popper's notion of scientific discovery by refutation. Our framework rests on the assumption of a restricted class of structures in (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can there be a Bayesian explanationism? On the prospects of a productive partnership.Frank Cabrera - 2017 - Synthese 194 (4):1245–1272.
    In this paper, I consider the relationship between Inference to the Best Explanation and Bayesianism, both of which are well-known accounts of the nature of scientific inference. In Sect. 2, I give a brief overview of Bayesianism and IBE. In Sect. 3, I argue that IBE in its most prominently defended forms is difficult to reconcile with Bayesianism because not all of the items that feature on popular lists of “explanatory virtues”—by means of which IBE ranks competing explanations—have confirmational import. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Assessing Theories: The Coherentist Approach.Peter Brössel - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (3):593-623.
    In this paper we show that the coherence measures of Olsson (J Philos 94:246–272, 2002), Shogenji (Log Anal 59:338–345, 1999), and Fitelson (Log Anal 63:194–199, 2003) satisfy the two most important adequacy requirements for the purpose of assessing theories. Following Hempel (Synthese 12:439–469, 1960), Levi (Gambling with truth, New York, A. A. Knopf, 1967), and recently Huber (Synthese 161:89–118, 2008) we require, as minimal or necessary conditions, that adequate assessment functions favor true theories over false theories and true and informative (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures.Patrick Suppes - 2002 - CSLI Publications (distributed by Chicago University Press).
    An early, very preliminary edition of this book was circulated in 1962 under the title Set-theoretical Structures in Science. There are many reasons for maintaining that such structures play a role in the philosophy of science. Perhaps the best is that they provide the right setting for investigating problems of representation and invariance in any systematic part of science, past or present. Examples are easy to cite. Sophisticated analysis of the nature of representation in perception is to be found already (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations