Switch to: References

Citations of:

Intuitionism

Amsterdam,: North-Holland Pub. Co. (1956)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Proofs and Retributions, Or: Why Sarah Can’t Take Limits.Vladimir Kanovei, Karin U. Katz, Mikhail G. Katz & Mary Schaps - 2015 - Foundations of Science 20 (1):1-25.
    The small, the tiny, and the infinitesimal have been the object of both fascination and vilification for millenia. One of the most vitriolic reviews in mathematics was that written by Errett Bishop about Keisler’s book Elementary Calculus: an Infinitesimal Approach. In this skit we investigate both the argument itself, and some of its roots in Bishop George Berkeley’s criticism of Leibnizian and Newtonian Calculus. We also explore some of the consequences to students for whom the infinitesimal approach is congenial. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The surprise examination on the paradox of the Heap.Joseph Wayne Smith - 1984 - Philosophical Papers 13 (1):43-56.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Epistemology Versus Ontology: Essays on the Philosophy and Foundations of Mathematics in Honour of Per Martin-Löf.Peter Dybjer, Sten Lindström, Erik Palmgren & Göran Sundholm (eds.) - 2012 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This book brings together philosophers, mathematicians and logicians to penetrate important problems in the philosophy and foundations of mathematics. In philosophy, one has been concerned with the opposition between constructivism and classical mathematics and the different ontological and epistemological views that are reflected in this opposition. The dominant foundational framework for current mathematics is classical logic and set theory with the axiom of choice. This framework is, however, laden with philosophical difficulties. One important alternative foundational programme that is actively pursued (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Difficulties of demonstrating the possession of concepts.Ernst von Glasersfeld - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):601-602.
  • A Kuroda-style j-translation.Benno van den Berg - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (5):627-634.
    A nucleus is an operation on the collection of truth values which, like double negation in intuitionistic logic, is monotone, inflationary, idempotent and commutes with conjunction. Any nucleus determines a proof-theoretic translation of intuitionistic logic into itself by applying it to atomic formulas, disjunctions and existentially quantified subformulas, as in the Gödel–Gentzen negative translation. Here we show that there exists a similar translation of intuitionistic logic into itself which is more in the spirit of Kuroda’s negative translation. The key is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On a second order propositional operator in intuitionistic logic.A. S. Troelstra - 1981 - Studia Logica 40 (2):113 - 139.
    This paper studies, by way of an example, the intuitionistic propositional connective * defined in the language of second order propositional logic by. In full topological models * is not generally definable, but over Cantor-space and the reals it can be classically shown that; on the other hand, this is false constructively, i.e. a contradiction with Church's thesis is obtained. This is comparable with some well-known results on the completeness of intuitionistic first-order predicate logic.Over [0, 1], the operator * is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On a second order propositional operator in intuitionistic logic.A. A. Troelstra - 1981 - Studia Logica 40:113.
    This paper studies, by way of an example, the intuitionistic propositional connective * defined in the language of second order propositional logic by * ≡ ∃Q. In full topological models * is not generally definable but over Cantor-space and the reals it can be classically shown that *↔ ⅂⅂P; on the other hand, this is false constructively, i.e. a contradiction with Church's thesis is obtained. This is comparable with some well-known results on the completeness of intuitionistic first-order predicate logic. Over (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • To honor Davis & Pérusse and repeal their glossary of processes of numerical competence.Roger K. Thomas - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):600-600.
  • Problems of axiomatics and complexity in studying numerical competence in animals.Patrick Suppes - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):599-599.
  • Possibilities for the construction of a sense of number by animals.Leslie P. Steffe - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):598-599.
  • On the concept of language in some recent theories of meaning.Sören Stenlund - 1989 - Synthese 79 (1):51 - 98.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Competitive equilibrium with intuitionistic agents.Jack Douglas Stecher - 2011 - Synthese 181 (S1):49 - 63.
    This paper studies an economy whose agents perceive their consumption possibilities subjectively, and whose preferences are defined on what they subjectively experience, rather than on those alternatives that are objectively present. The model of agents' perceptions is based on intuitionistic logic. Roughly, this means that agents reason constructively: a solution to a problem exists only if there is a construction by which the problem can be solved. The theorems that can be proved determine how an agent perceives a set of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Locatedness and overt sublocales.Bas Spitters - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (1):36-54.
    Locatedness is one of the fundamental notions in constructive mathematics. The existence of a positivity predicate on a locale, i.e. the locale being overt, or open, has proved to be fundamental in constructive locale theory. We show that the two notions are intimately connected.Bishop defines a metric space to be compact if it is complete and totally bounded. A subset of a totally bounded set is again totally bounded iff it is located. So a closed subset of a Bishop compact (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Objectivity of Mathematics.Stewart Shapiro - 2007 - Synthese 156 (2):337-381.
    The purpose of this paper is to apply Crispin Wright’s criteria and various axes of objectivity to mathematics. I test the criteria and the objectivity of mathematics against each other. Along the way, various issues concerning general logic and epistemology are encountered.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Logic, ontology, mathematical practice.Stewart Shapiro - 1989 - Synthese 79 (1):13 - 50.
  • Are animals naturally attuned to number?Uta Seibt - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):597-598.
  • Language and counting in animals: Stimulus classes and equivalence relations.Ronald J. Schusterman - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):596-597.
  • On the Coherence of Wittgensteinian Constructivism.Amit Saad - 2016 - Acta Analytica 31 (4):455-462.
    Michael Dummett presents a modus tollens argument against a Wittgensteinian conception of meaning. In a series of papers, Dummett claims that Wittgensteinian considerations entail strict finitism. However, by a “sorites argument”, Dummett argues that strict finitism is incoherent and therefore questions these Wittgensteinian considerations.In this paper, I will argue that Dummett’s sorites argument fails to undermine strict finitism. I will claim that the argument is based on two questionable assumptions regarding some strict finitist sets of natural numbers. It will be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reply to Øystein Linnebo and Stewart Shapiro.Ian Rumfitt - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (7):842-858.
    ABSTRACTIn reply to Linnebo, I defend my analysis of Tait's argument against the use of classical logic in set theory, and make some preliminary comments on Linnebo's new argument for the same conclusion. I then turn to Shapiro's discussion of intuitionistic analysis and of Smooth Infinitesimal Analysis. I contend that we can make sense of intuitionistic analysis, but only by attaching deviant meanings to the connectives. Whether anyone can make sense of SIA is open to doubt: doing so would involve (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rings and Fields, a Constructive View.Daniel A. Romano - 1988 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 34 (1):25-40.
  • Rings and Fields, a Constructive View.Daniel A. Romano - 1988 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 34 (1):25-40.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intuitionism, Meaning Theory and Cognition.Richard Tieszen - 2000 - History and Philosophy of Logic 21 (3):179-194.
    Michael Dummett has interpreted and expounded upon intuitionism under the influence of Wittgensteinian views on language, meaning and cognition. I argue against the application of some of these views to intuitionism and point to shortcomings in Dummett's approach. The alternative I propose makes use of recent, post-Wittgensteinian views in the philosophy of mind, meaning and language. These views are associated with the claim that human cognition exhibits intentionality and with related ideas in philosophical psychology. Intuitionism holds that mathematical constructions are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Truth Values and Proof Theory.Greg Restall - 2009 - Studia Logica 92 (2):241-264.
    I present an account of truth values for classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and the modal logic S5, in which truth values are not a fundamental category from which the logic is defined, but rather, an idealisation of more fundamental logical features in the proof theory for each system. The result is not a new set of semantic structures, but a new understanding of how the existing semantic structures may be understood in terms of a more fundamental notion of logical consequence.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Intuitionistic truth.Wlodzimierz Rabinowicz - 1985 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 14 (2):191 - 228.
  • The theory of empirical sequences.Carl J. Posy - 1977 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1):47 - 81.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Studying numerical competence: A trip through linguistic wonderland?Irene M. Pepperberg - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):595-596.
  • Reinforcement schedules and “numerical competence”.John A. Nevin - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):594-595.
  • Epistemic logic: All knowledge is based on our experience, and epistemic logic is the cognitive representation of our experiential confrontation in reality.Dan Nesher - 2021 - Semiotica 2021 (238):153-179.
    Epistemic Logic is our basic universal science, the method of our cognitive confrontation in reality to prove the truth of our basic cognitions and theories. Hence, by proving their true representation of reality we can self-control ourselves in it, and thus refuting the Berkeleyian solipsism and Kantian a priorism. The conception of epistemic logic is that only by proving our true representation of reality we achieve our knowledge of it, and thus we can prove our cognitions to be either true (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A complete negationless system.David Nelson - 1973 - Studia Logica 32 (1):41 - 49.
  • Logical foundations of applied mathematics.V. V. Nalimov - 1974 - Synthese 27 (1-2):211 - 250.
    In applied problems mathematics is used as language or as a metalanguage on which metatheories are built, E.G., Mathematical theory of experiment. The structure of pure mathematics is grammar of the language. As opposed to pure mathematics, In applied problems we must keep in mind what underlies the sign system. Optimality criteria-Axioms of applied mathematics-Prove mutually incompatible, They form a mosaic and not mathematical structures which, According to bourbaki, Make mathematics a unified science. One of the peculiarities of applied mathematical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Penser la négation: une introduction. [REVIEW]Denis Miéville - 1992 - Argumentation 6 (1):1-6.
  • Heyting’s contribution to the change in research into the foundations of mathematics.Miriam Franchella - 1994 - History and Philosophy of Logic 15 (2):149-172.
    After the 1930s, the research into the foundations of mathematics changed.None of its main directions (logicism, formalism and intuitionism) had any longer the pretension to be the only true mathematics.Usually, the determining factor in the change is considered to be Gödel?s work, while Heyting?s role is neglected.In contrast, in this paper I first describe how Heyting directly suggested the abandonment of the big foundational questions and the putting forward of a new kind of foundational research consisting in the isolation of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is it the thought that counts?Brendan McGonigle - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):593-594.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sur une extension simple du calcul intuitionniste Des predicats du premier ordre appliquee a l'analyse.Maurice Margenstern - 1984 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 30 (19‐24):317-324.
  • Sur Une Extension Simple du Calcul Intuitionniste Des Predicats du Premier Ordre Appliquee a L'Analyse.Maurice Margenstern - 1984 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 30 (19-24):317-324.
  • Negationless intuitionism.Enrico Martino - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (2):165-177.
    The present paper deals with natural intuitionistic semantics for intuitionistic logic within an intuitionistic metamathematics. We show how strong completeness of full first order logic fails. We then consider a negationless semantics à la Henkin for second order intuitionistic logic. By using the theory of lawless sequences we prove that, for such semantics, strong completeness is restorable. We argue that lawless negationless semantics is a suitable framework for a constructive structuralist interpretation of any second order formalizable theory (classical or intuitionistic, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructively Complete Finite Sets.Mark Mandelkern - 1988 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 34 (2):97-103.
  • Constructively Complete Finite Sets.Mark Mandelkern - 1988 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 34 (2):97-103.
  • Intuitionistic mereology.Paolo Maffezioli & Achille C. Varzi - 2021 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 18):4277-4302.
    Two mereological theories are presented based on a primitive apartness relation along with binary relations of mereological excess and weak excess, respectively. It is shown that both theories are acceptable from the standpoint of constructive reasoning while remaining faithful to the spirit of classical mereology. The two theories are then compared and assessed with regard to their extensional import.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • You can't succeed without really counting.Euan M. Macphail - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):592-593.
  • Wilson on relativism and teaching.Jim Mackenzie - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 21 (1):119–130.
    Jim Mackenzie; Wilson on Relativism and Teaching, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 21, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 119–130, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Numbers and counting: Intuitionistic and gestalt psychological viewpoints.Abraham S. Luchins & Edith H. Luchins - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):591-592.
  • Constructions and negationless logic.E. G. K. López-Escobar - 1972 - Studia Logica 30 (1):7 - 22.
  • Introduction to special issue on ‘critical views of logic’.Øystein Linnebo, Frode Kjosavik & Mirja Hartimo - 2022 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 65 (6):631-637.
    Critical views of logic are presented. These are views that are critical of logic in a sense akin to the way in which Kant is critical rather than dogmatic about traditional metaphysics. Such approaches differ from the Fregean ‘logic-first’ view. In accordance with the latter, logic is often regarded as epistemologically and methodologically fundamental. Hence, all disciplines – including mathematics – are considered as answerable to logic, rather than vice versa. In critical views of logic, by contrast, the logical principles (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Number reckoning strategies: A basis for distinction.Eugene C. Lechelt - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):590-591.
  • Some Obstacles Facing a Semantic Foundation for Constructive Mathematics.Michael R. Koss - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (5):1055-1068.
    This paper discusses Michael Dummett’s attempt to base the use of intuitionistic logic in mathematics on a proof-conditional semantics. This project is shown to face significant obstacles resulting from the existence of variants of standard intuitionistic logic. In order to overcome these obstacles, Dummett and his followers must give an intuitionistically acceptable completeness proof for intuitionistic logic relative to the BHK interpretation of the logical constants, but there are reasons to doubt that such a proof is possible. The paper concludes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Number concepts in animals: A multidimensional array.James E. King - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):590-590.
  • A New Approach to Constructive Topology and Measure Theory.A. K. Khalifa - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (6):539-550.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A New Approach to Constructive Topology and Measure Theory.A. K. Khalifa - 1989 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 35 (6):539-550.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Burgessian Critique of Nominalistic Tendencies in Contemporary Mathematics and its Historiography.Karin Usadi Katz & Mikhail G. Katz - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (1):51-89.
    We analyze the developments in mathematical rigor from the viewpoint of a Burgessian critique of nominalistic reconstructions. We apply such a critique to the reconstruction of infinitesimal analysis accomplished through the efforts of Cantor, Dedekind, and Weierstrass; to the reconstruction of Cauchy’s foundational work associated with the work of Boyer and Grabiner; and to Bishop’s constructivist reconstruction of classical analysis. We examine the effects of a nominalist disposition on historiography, teaching, and research.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations