Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On the possibilities of group injury.Stephen Winter - 2006 - Metaphilosophy 37 (3-4):393–413.
    Normative discourse on genocide frequently refers to group injuries, but this can be problematic for those for whom normative justification ought, in principle, to be reducible to individual terms. Such ethical individualists may hold that an ultimately individualizable description of injury is always theoretically superior (in lacking either superfluous or ontologically suspect entities). Accepting the strictures of individualistic justification, this paper presumes that attributing injury to group subjects will be unsatisfying if this attribution does not include a normatively significant group (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Paradox of Public Interest: How Serving Individual Superior Interests Fulfill Public Relations' Obligation to the Public Interest.Kevin Stoker & Megan Stoker - 2012 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 27 (1):31-45.
    Since the early 20th century, advocates of public relations professionalism have mandated that practitioners serve the public interest making it an ethical standard for evaluating the morality of public relations practice. However, the field has devoted little research to determining just what it means for practitioners to serve the public interest. Most research suggests practice-oriented solutions. This article focuses what practitioners must do to serve the public interest. It reviews theories of the social contract and the public interest to identify (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Concepts of Common Good and Public Interest: From Plato to Biobanking.Kadri Simm - 2011 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 20 (4):554-562.
    The expression “common good” usually conjures up benevolent associations: it is something to be desired, a worthy goal, and it would be a brave person who declared he or she was against the common good. Yet modern times have taught us to be critical and even suspicious of such grand rhetoric, leading us to query what lies behind this ambitious notion, who formulates what it stands for, and how such formulations have been reached.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A justification of whistleblowing.Daniele Santoro & Manohar Kumar - 2017 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 43 (7):669-684.
    Whistleblowing is the act of disclosing information from a public or private organization in order to reveal cases of corruption that are of immediate or potential danger to the public. Blowing the whistle involves personal risk, especially when legal protection is absent, and charges of betrayal, which often come in the form of legal prosecution under treason laws. In this article we argue that whistleblowing is justified when disclosures are made with the proper intent and fulfill specific communicative constraints in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Deliberating about the public interest.Ian O’Flynn - 2010 - Res Publica 16 (3):299-315.
    Although the idea of the public interest features prominently in many accounts of deliberative democracy, the relationship between deliberative democracy and the public interest is rarely spelt out with any degree of precision. In this article, I identify and defend one particular way of framing this relationship. I begin by arguing that people can deliberate about the public interest only if the public interest is, in principle, identifiable independently of their deliberations. Of course, some pluralists claim that the public interest (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The place of self-interest and the role of power in deliberative democracy.Jane Mansbridge, James Bohman, Simone Chambers, David Estlund, Andreas Føllesdal, Archon Fung, Cristina Lafont, Bernard Manin & José Luis Martí - 2009 - Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (1):64-100.
  • Constitutional conscience: Criminal justice and public interest ethics.Bradley Stewart Chilton - 1998 - Criminal Justice Ethics 17 (2):33-41.
    (1998). Constitutional conscience: Criminal justice and public interest ethics. Criminal Justice Ethics: Vol. 17, No. 2, pp. 33-41. doi: 10.1080/0731129X.1998.9992056.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark