Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Lines of Descent: Kuhn and Beyond.Friedel Weinert - 2014 - Foundations of Science 19 (4):331-352.
    Thomas S. Kuhn is famous both for his work on the Copernican Revolution and his ‘paradigm’ view of scientific revolutions. But Kuhn later abandoned the notion of paradigm in favour of a more ‘evolutionary’ view of the history of science. Kuhn’s position therefore moved closer to ‘continuity’ models of scientific progress, for instance ‘chain-of-reasoning’ models, originally championed by D. Shapere. The purpose of this paper is to contribute to the debate around Kuhn’s new ‘developmental’ view and to evaluate these competing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Could Lakatos, even with Zahar's criterion for novel fact, evaluate the copernican research programme?Neil Thomason - 1992 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (2):161-200.
    Why did Copernicus's research programme supersede Ptolemy's?’, Lakatos and Zahar argued that, on Zahar's criterion for ‘novel fact’, Copernican theory was objectively scientifically superior to Ptolemaic theory. They are mistaken, Lakatos and Zahar applied Zahar's criterion to ‘a historical thought-experiment’—fictional rather than real history. Further, in their fictional history, they compared Copernicus to Eudoxus rather than Ptolemy, ignored Tycho Brahe, and did not consider facts that would be novel for geostatic theories. When Zahar's criterion is applied to real history, the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The importance of historical accuracy in philosophy of science: The case of Curd's conception of copernican rationality.Keith A. Nier - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (3):372-394.
    General discussions of the appropriate relations between history and philosophy of science must be complemented by examinations of particular studies involving both fields. Martin Curd's attempt to illuminate the rationality of theory change through analysis of the Copernican Revolution is such a study; his work is undercut by serious flaws and actually displays an ahistorical approach. The result misleads both about the Copernican Revolution and the general problem of theory change in science. The study does illustrate several types of failing (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scientific change: Philosophical models and historical research.Larry Laudan, Arthur Donovan, Rachel Laudan, Peter Barker, Harold Brown, Jarrett Leplin, Paul Thagard & Steve Wykstra - 1986 - Synthese 69 (2):141 - 223.
  • Towards an empirically adequate theory of science.Janet A. Kourany - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (4):526-548.
    While there has been general agreement among modern philosophers of science that a purely a priori method is inappropriate to the task of establishing a theory of science, there has, unfortunately, been little comparable agreement regarding the method that is appropriate. I try to lay the foundations for such agreement. I first set out reasons for a purely empirical method for establishing a theory of science, and defend such a method against charges raised by Giere. I then develop some very (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Copernican Revolution revisited: paradigm, metaphor and incommensurability in the history of science- Blumenberg's response to Kuhn and Davidson.David Ingram - 1993 - History of the Human Sciences 6 (4):11-35.
  • Context of discovery and context of justification.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 1986 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (4):501-515.
  • The Role of Comets in The Copernican Revolution.Peter Barker - 1988 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 19 (3):299.