Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Weirdness of the World.Eric Schwitzgebel - 2024 - Princeton University Press.
    How all philosophical explanations of human consciousness and the fundamental structure of the cosmos are bizarre—and why that’s a good thing Do we live inside a simulated reality or a pocket universe embedded in a larger structure about which we know virtually nothing? Is consciousness a purely physical matter, or might it require something extra, something nonphysical? According to the philosopher Eric Schwitzgebel, it’s hard to say. In The Weirdness of the World, Schwitzgebel argues that the answers to these fundamental (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Systematic, idiosyncratic reaching errors.David Zipser - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):353-354.
  • Only half way up.Andrew W. Young - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):558-558.
  • Distance errors: Pointing to the range effect.Charles J. Worringham & Robert G. Dennis - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):352-353.
  • The primary visual system does not care about Previc's near-far dichotomy. Why not?Robert W. Williams - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):557-558.
  • Reaching the point where you have to move a head.John Wann - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):351-352.
  • Sense of body and sense of action both contribute to self-recognition.Esther van den Bos & Marc Jeannerod - 2002 - Cognition 85 (2):177-187.
  • Approximations might lead to errors in brain science.James P. Trevelyan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):350-351.
  • The Spatial Content of Experience.Brad Thompson - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1):146-184.
    To what extent is the external world the way that it appears to us in perceptual experience? This perennial question in philosophy is no doubt ambiguous in many ways. For example, it might be taken as equivalent to the question of whether or not the external world is the way that it appears to be? This is a question about the epistemology of perception: Are our perceptual experiences by and large veridical representations of the external world? Alternatively, the question might (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Different regions of space or different spaces altogether: What are the dorsal/ventral systems processing?Gary W. Strong - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):556-557.
  • In the dark about pointing: What's the point?John F. Soechting, Stephen I. Helms Tillery & Martha Flanders - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):354-362.
  • Properties of neurons in the dorsal visual pathway of the monkey.Ralph M. Siegel - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):555-556.
  • The Problem of Known Illusion and the Resemblance of Experience to Reality.Eric Schwitzgebel - 2014 - Philosophy of Science 81 (5):954-960.
    Are objects in convex passenger-side mirrors “closer than they appear”? If one adapts to inverting goggles, does the world go back to looking the way it was before, or does the world look approximately the same throughout the course of adaptation, only losing its normative sense of wrongness? The answers to these empirical, introspective questions might help cast light on the classic philosophical debate about the degree of resemblance between our visual experience of reality and things as they are in (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Simultaneous visual adaptation to tilt and displacement: A test of independent processes.Gordon M. Redding - 1973 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 2 (1):41-42.
  • Visual processing in three-dimensional space: Perceptions and misperceptions.Fred H. Previc - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):559-575.
  • Perceptual precision.Adrienne Prettyman - 2019 - Philosophical Psychology 32 (6):923-944.
    ABSTRACTThe standard view in philosophy of mind is that the way to understand the difference between perception and misperception is in terms of accuracy. On this view, perception is accurate while...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Functional specialization in the lower and upper visual fields in humans: Its ecological origins and neurophysiological implications.Fred H. Previc - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):519-542.
  • S-O-R: Wrong model for pointing.William T. Powers - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):349-350.
  • Coordinate transformations in orofacial movements.D. J. Ostry, J. R. Flanagan & L. E. Sergio - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):348-349.
  • Peripheral lower visual fields: A neglected factor?Naoyuki Osaka - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):555-555.
  • A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness.J. Kevin O’Regan & Alva Noë - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (5):883-917.
    Many current neurophysiological, psychophysical, and psychological approaches to vision rest on the idea that when we see, the brain produces an internal representation of the world. The activation of this internal representation is assumed to give rise to the experience of seeing. The problem with this kind of approach is that it leaves unexplained how the existence of such a detailed internal representation might produce visual consciousness. An alternative proposal is made here. We propose that seeing is a way of (...)
    Direct download (16 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   732 citations  
  • Coordinate transformations or dynamic models?Peter D. Neilson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):348-348.
  • Energy, information, detection, and action.Claire F. Michaels & Raoul R. D. Oudejans - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (2):230-230.
    Before one can talk about global arrays and multimodal detection, one must be clear about the concept of information: How is it different from energy and how is it detected? And can it come to specify a needed movement? We consider these issues in our commentary.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Invariants of the second transformation expressed in activation ranges.Gin McCollum - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):346-348.
  • Coordinate transformations: Some basic questions.Lina L. E. Massone - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):345-346.
  • Why the computations must not be ignored.Chad J. Marsolek - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):554-555.
  • Simultaneous right- and left-hand adaptation in opposite lateral directions following bidirectional optical displacement.Lydia M. Martin & Colin V. Newman - 1980 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 16 (6):432-434.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Coordinate transformations in postural control.Francesco Lacquaniti - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):345-345.
  • The role of dorsal/ventral processing dissociation in the economy of the primate brain.Marcel Kinsbourne & Charles J. Duffy - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):553-554.
  • Limitations on the what reaching can tell us about sensorimotor transformations.Michael Kalish - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):344-344.
  • Agency, simulation and self-identification.Marc Jeannerod & Elisabeth Pacherie - 2004 - Mind and Language 19 (2):113-146.
    This paper is concerned with the problem of selfidentification in the domain of action. We claim that this problem can arise not just for the self as object, but also for the self as subject in the ascription of agency. We discuss and evaluate some proposals concerning the mechanisms involved in selfidentification and in agencyascription, and their possible impairments in pathological cases. We argue in favor of a simulation hypothesis that claims that actions, whether overt or covert, are centrally simulated (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Perception and action: Alternative views.Susan Hurley - 2001 - Synthese 129 (1):3-40.
    A traditional view of perception and action makestwo assumptions: that the causal flow betweenperception and action is primarily linear or one-way,and that they are merely instrumentally related toeach other, so that each is a means to the other.Either or both of these assumptions can be rejected. Behaviorism rejects the instrumental but not theone-way aspect of the traditional view, thus leavingitself open to charges of verificationism. Ecologicalviews reject the one-way aspect but not theinstrumental aspect of the traditional view, so thatperception and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Neural plasticity and consciousness.Susan Hurley & Alva Noë - 2003 - Biology and Philosophy 18 (1):131-168.
    and apply it to various examples of neural plasticity in which input is rerouted intermodally or intramodally to nonstandard cortical targets. In some cases but not others, cortical activity ‘defers’ to the nonstandard sources of input. We ask why, consider some possible explanations, and propose a dynamic sensorimotor hypothesis. We believe that this distinction is important and worthy of further study, both philosophical and empirical, whether or not our hypothesis turns out to be correct. In particular, the question of how (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Information decay during response delay.Dennis H. Holding - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):343-344.
  • Attention to near and far space: The third dichotomy.Kenneth M. Heilman, Dawn Bowers & Paul Shelton - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):552-553.
  • Physical modeling applies to physiology, too.Vincent Hayward - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):342-343.
    A physical model was utilized to show that the neural system can memorize a target position and is able to cause motor and sensory events that move the arm to a target with more accuracy. However, this cannot indicate in which coordinates the necessary computations are carried out. Turning off the lights causes the error to increase which is accomplished by cutting off one feedback path. The geometrical properties of arm kinematics and the properties of the kinesthetic and visual sensorial (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are errors in final position destined before the movement begins?Z. Hasan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):341-342.
  • Adaptation to displaced vision: A change in the central control of sensorimotor coordination.Martha E. Hardt, Richard Held & Martin J. Steinbach - 1971 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 89 (2):229.
  • Motor-sensory feedback and geometry of visual space: an attempted replication.John Gyr, Richmond Willey & Adele Henry - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):59-64.
  • Central spatial representations and mapping the sensorimotor interface: How early is early, how late is late, and what difference does it all make anyhow?Paul Grobstein - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):339-341.
  • In reaching, the task is to move the hand to a target.J. Gordon, M. F. Ghilardi & C. Ghez - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):337-339.
  • Pigeons, primates, and division of labor in the vertebrate visual system.M. A. Goodale & J. A. Graves - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):551-552.
  • Now you see it, now you don't: How delaying an action system can transform a theory.Melvyn A. Goodale & Philip Servos - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):335-336.
  • In Defence of David Armstrong's Materialist Theory of Perception.D. Goldstick - 2021 - Dialogue 60 (2):379-394.
    RÉSUMÉLes qualia n'existent pas. La différence phénoménologique entre voir et imaginer, c'est que les propositions auxquelles l'expérient commence à croire dans le premier cas sont uniquement considérées dans le second. Nous pouvons savoir «quel effet cela fait d’être une chauve-souris» en sachant que leur faculté d’écholocation les informe non-inférentiellement des formes, grandeurs, et distances directionnelles des surfaces à proximité. Toutefois, les termes désignant les qualités secondes (comme les couleurs) sont les noms des propriétés-types qu'ils désignent, et dérivent causalement d'un «baptême» (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kinesthesia and unique solutions for control of multijoint movements.S. C. Gandevia - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):335-335.
  • Early stages in a sensorimotor transformation.Martha Flanders, Stephen I. Helms Tillery & John F. Soechting - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):309-320.
    We present a model for several early stages of the sensorimotor transformations involved in targeted arm movement. In psychophysical experiments, human subjects pointed to the remembered locations of randomly placed targets in three-dimensional space. They made consistent errors in distance, and from these errors stages in the sensorimotor transformation were deduced. When subjects attempted to move the right index finger to a virtual target they consistently undershot the distance of the more distal targets. Other experiments indicated that the error was (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Ecology and functional specialization: The whole is less than the sum of the parts.John M. Findlay - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):551-551.
  • Nuevos dispositivos electrónicos para interaccionar con el sistema nervioso.Eduardo Fernández Jover - 2004 - Arbor 177 (698):311-335.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perceptual Similarity: Insights From Crossmodal Correspondences.Nicola Di Stefano & Charles Spence - forthcoming - Review of Philosophy and Psychology:1-30.
    Perceptual similarity is one of the most fiercely debated topics in the philosophy and psychology of perception. The documented history of the issue spans all the way from Plato – who regarded similarity as a key factor for human perceptual experience and cognition – through to contemporary psychologists – who have tried to determine whether, and if so, how similarity relationships can be established between stimuli both within and across the senses. Recent research on cross-sensory associations, otherwise known as crossmodal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Through the inverting glass: first-person observations on spatial vision and imagery. [REVIEW]Jan Degenaar - 2014 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13 (2):373-393.
    Experience with inverting glasses reveals key factors of spatial vision. Interpretations of the literature based on the metaphor of a “visual image” have raised the question whether visual experience with inverting glasses remains inverted or whether it may turn back to normal after adaptation to the glasses. Here, I report on my experience with left/right inverting glasses and argue that a more fine-grained sensorimotor analysis can resolve the issue. Crucially, inverting glasses introduce a conflict at the very heart of spatial (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations