Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Analyzing the degree of conflict among belief functions.Weiru Liu - 2006 - Artificial Intelligence 170 (11):909--924.
  • Belief functions on distributive lattices.Chunlai Zhou - 2013 - Artificial Intelligence 201 (C):1-31.
  • Measures of uncertainty in expert systems.Peter Walley - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 83 (1):1-58.
  • The transferable belief model.Philippe Smets & Robert Kennes - 1994 - Artificial Intelligence 66 (2):191-234.
  • Agent-oriented epistemic reasoning: Subjective conditions of knowledge and belief.Daniel G. Schwartz - 2003 - Artificial Intelligence 148 (1-2):177-195.
  • Strong Completeness Theorems for Weak Logics of Common Belief.Lismont Luc & Mongin Philippe - 2003 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (2):115-137.
    We show that several logics of common belief and common knowledge are not only complete, but also strongly complete, hence compact. These logics involve a weakened monotonicity axiom, and no other restriction on individual belief. The semantics is of the ordinary fixed-point type.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Common knowledge: Relating anti-founded situation semantics to modal logic neighbourhood semantics. [REVIEW]L. Lismont - 1994 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 3 (4):285-302.
    Two approaches for defining common knowledge coexist in the literature: the infinite iteration definition and the circular or fixed point one. In particular, an original modelization of the fixed point definition was proposed by Barwise in the context of a non-well-founded set theory and the infinite iteration approach has been technically analyzed within multi-modal epistemic logic using neighbourhood semantics by Lismont. This paper exhibits a relation between these two ways of modelling common knowledge which seem at first quite different.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The consensus operator for combining beliefs.Audun Jøsang - 2002 - Artificial Intelligence 141 (1-2):157-170.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evidence with uncertain likelihoods.Joseph Halpern & Riccardo Pucella - 2009 - Synthese 171 (1):111-133.
    An agent often has a number of hypotheses, and must choose among them based on observations, or outcomes of experiments. Each of these observations can be viewed as providing evidence for or against various hypotheses. All the attempts to formalize this intuition up to now have assumed that associated with each hypothesis h there is a likelihood function μ h , which is a probability measure that intuitively describes how likely each observation is, conditional on h being the correct hypothesis. (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Probabilistic Logics and Probabilistic Networks.Rolf Haenni, Jan-Willem Romeijn, Gregory Wheeler & Jon Williamson - 2010 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Synthese Library. Edited by Gregory Wheeler, Rolf Haenni, Jan-Willem Romeijn & and Jon Williamson.
    Additionally, the text shows how to develop computationally feasible methods to mesh with this framework.
  • Credal networks.Fabio G. Cozman - 2000 - Artificial Intelligence 120 (2):199-233.
  • A minimal extension of Bayesian decision theory.Ken Binmore - 2016 - Theory and Decision 80 (3):341-362.
    Savage denied that Bayesian decision theory applies in large worlds. This paper proposes a minimal extension of Bayesian decision theory to a large-world context that evaluates an event E\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$E$$\end{document} by assigning it a number π\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\pi $$\end{document} that reduces to an orthodox probability for a class of measurable events. The Hurwicz criterion evaluates π\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\pi $$\end{document} (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Modelling learning as modelling.Scott Moss & Bruce Edmonds - unknown
    Economists tend to represent learning as a procedure for estimating the parameters of the "correct" econometric model. We extend this approach by assuming that agents specify as well as estimate models. Learning thus takes the form of a dynamic process of developing models using an internal language of representation where expectations are formed by forecasting with the best current model. This introduces a distinction between the form and content of the internal models which is particularly relevant for boundedly rational agents. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation