Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Making the audience: Ekphrasis and rhetorical strategy in demosthenes 18 and 19.Andreas Serafim - 2015 - Classical Quarterly 65 (1):96-108.
    In this paper, I intend to explore three examples ofekphrasis– narrative scene painting – in Demosthenes 18 and 19: the first is Demosthenes' depiction of the announcement in Athens of the capture of Elatea by Philip, while the second and third are descriptions of Aeschines' failed theatrical performances. Scholars have paid insufficient attention to these descriptive accounts: there have been a few limited discussions of 18.169 in commentaries but, otherwise, the use and purpose of these accounts as part of Demosthenes' (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • He who laughs last – Jesus and laughter in the Synoptic and Gnostic traditions.Marius J. Nel - 2014 - HTS Theological Studies 70 (1).
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • As If We Were Codgers: Flattery, Parrhēsia and Old Man Demos in Aristophanes’ Knights.Elizabeth Markovits - 2012 - Polis 29 (1):108-129.
    In Knights, Aristophanes represents the dangers of parrhēsia run amuck with the near-destruction of an elderly man’s Athenian household by Paphlagon. In this setting, Paphlagon’s invocations of his own parrhēsia and goodwill become a destructive form of flattery, causing chaos in the household and threatening its viability. This article begins with a discussion of the problem of parrhēsia in democratic Athens and the ways in which Cleon exemplified those problems. Moving to an examination of Aristophanes’ Knights, the author tracks the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Emperors’ Nicknames and Roman Political Humour.Alexander V. Makhlaiuk - 2020 - Klio 102 (1):202-235.
    Summary The article examines unofficial imperial nicknames, sobriquets and appellatives, from Octavian Augustus to Julian the Apostate, in the light of traditions of Roman political humour, and argues that in the political field during the Principate there were two co-existing competing modes of emperors’ naming: along with an official one, politically loyal, formalised and institutionally legitimised, there existed another – unofficial, sometimes oppositional and even hostile towards individual emperors, frequently licentious, humorously coloured and, in this regard, deeply rooted in Roman (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Phenomenology of Democracy.Paul J. Kosmin - 2015 - Classical Antiquity 34 (1):121-162.
    This article has two objectives. First, and in particular, it seeks to reinterpret the ostracism procedure of early democratic Athens. Since Aristotle, this has been understood as a rational, political weapon of collective defense, intended to expel from Athens a disproportionately powerful individual. In this article, by putting emphasis on themateriality, gestures, and location of ostraka-casting, I propose instead that the institution can more fruitfully be understood as a ritual enactment of civic unity. Second, and more generally, I hope to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kina[I]dos: A pun in demosthenes’ on the crown?Deborah Kamen - 2014 - Classical Quarterly 64 (1):405-408.
    In his speech On the Crown , the orator Demosthenes twice refers to his opponent Aeschines as a kinados , both times in the context of accusing him of flattery and slandering in the service of Philip of Macedon . Although a number of scholars have studied the use of invective in the speeches of Demosthenes and Aeschines, very little attention has been paid to the significance of this peculiar epithet. In this note, I investigate why Demosthenes calls Aeschines a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The return of Hephaistos, Dionysiac procession ritual, and the creation of a visual narrative.Guy Hedreen - 2004 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 124:38-64.
    The return of Hephaistos to Olympos, as a myth, concerns the establishment of a balance of power among the Olympian gods. Many visual representations of the myth in Archaic and Classical Greek art give visible form to the same theme, but they do so in a manner entirely distinct from the manner in which it is expressed in literary narratives of the tale. In this paper, I argue that vase-painters incorporated elements of Dionysiac processional ritual into representations of the return (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Malice and the Ridiculous as Self-ignorance: A Dialectical Argument in Philebus 47d-50e.Rebecca Bensen Cain - 2017 - Southwest Philosophy Review 33 (1):83-94.
    Abstract: In the Philebus, Socrates constructs a dialectical argument in which he purports to explain to Protarchus why the pleasure that spectators feel when watching comedy is a mixture of pleasure and pain. To do this he brings in phthonos (malice or envy) as his prime example (47d-50e). I examine the argument and claim that Socrates implicitly challenges Protarchus’ beliefs about himself as moderate and self-knowing. I discuss two reasons to think that more is at stake in the argument than (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representaçoes do feminino no drama satírico.Tereza Virgínia Barbosa - 2008 - Humanitas 60:75-86.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristophanes vs. Socrates.Don Adams - 2014 - Dialogue 53 (4):691-713.
    Dans l’Apologiede Platon, Socrate affirme quephthonosetdiabolēont conduit Aristophane à devenir l’un de ses accusateurs. Soit Socrate commet une grossière exagération, car clairement Aristophane ne faisait que plaisanter, soit nous avons tort de penser que l’humour d’Aristophane n’est rien d’autre que de la plaisanterie. Dans cet article, je défends la seconde position. Je soutiens qu’Aristophane est un type spécifique de conservateur social et que Socrate était le genre de social-libéral qui dérangeait Aristophane. Je conclus queLes Nuéesn’est pas un texte innocent, mais (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • El orden de aparición de los personajes en los prólogos Aristofánicos y su función argumentativa.Maria Jimena Schere - 2013 - Revista de Estudios Clásicos 40:13-32.
    Las comedias de Aristófanes del periodo cleoniano, que se centran en polémicas políticas, emplean una misma técnica de apertura: el primer personaje protagónico que sale a escena en el prólogo representa la posición política defendida en la pieza y actúa como su principal portavoz. La prioridad en el orden de aparición genera en el público una empatía por los personajes que inauguran la obra porque estos acceden a un contacto inicial, cómplice, con el público y pueden asentar su postura antes (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark