Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Passive frame theory: A new synthesis.Ezequiel Morsella, Godwin Christine, Jantz Tiffany, Krieger Stephen & Gazzaley Adam - forthcoming - Behavioral and Brain Sciences.
    Passive frame theory attempts to illuminate what consciousness is, in mechanistic and functional terms; it does not address the “implementation” level of analysis (how neurons instantiate conscious states), an enigma for various disciplines. However, in response to the commentaries, we discuss how our framework provides clues regarding this enigma. In the framework, consciousness is passive albeit essential. Without consciousness, there would not be adaptive skeletomotor action.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Arguing from the Evidence.Brian A. Thomasson - 2011 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (4):495-534.
    In Kitzmiller v. Dover (2005), the only U.S. federal case on teaching Intelligent Design in public schools, the plaintiffs used the same argument as in the creation-science trials of the 1980s: Intelligent Design is religion, not science, because it invokes the supernatural; thus teaching it violates the Constitution. Although the plaintiffs won, this strategy is unwise because it is based on problematic definitions of religion and science, leads to multiple truths in society, and is unlikely to succeed before the present (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Arguing from the Evidence.Brian A. Thomasson - 2011 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (4):495-534.
    In Kitzmiller v. Dover (2005), the only U.S. federal case on teaching Intelligent Design in public schools, the plaintiffs used the same argument as in the creation-science trials of the 1980s: Intelligent Design is religion, not science, because it invokes the supernatural; thus teaching it violates the Constitution. Although the plaintiffs won, this strategy is unwise because it is based on problematic definitions of religion and science, leads to multiple truths in society, and is unlikely to succeed before the present (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Typology and Natural Kinds in Evo-Devo.Ingo Brigandt - 2021 - In Nuño De La Rosa Laura & Müller Gerd (eds.), Evolutionary Developmental Biology: A Reference Guide. Springer. pp. 483-493.
    The traditional practice of establishing morphological types and investigating morphological organization has found new support from evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo), especially with respect to the notion of body plans. Despite recurring claims that typology is at odds with evolutionary thinking, evo-devo offers mechanistic explanations of the evolutionary origin, transformation, and evolvability of morphological organization. In parallel, philosophers have developed non-essentialist conceptions of natural kinds that permit kinds to exhibit variation and undergo change. This not only facilitates a construal of species (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On mechanisms of cultural evolution, and the evolution of language and the common law.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):11-11.
  • Epigenesis and culture.Robert Fagen - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):10-10.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does play matter? Functional and evolutionary aspects of animal and human play.Peter K. Smith - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):139-155.
    In this paper I suggest that play is a distinctive behavioural category whose adaptive significance calls for explanation. Play primarily affords juveniles practice toward the exercise of later skills. Its benefits exceed its costs when sufficient practice would otherwise be unlikely or unsafe, as is particularly true with physical skills and socially competitive ones. Manipulative play with objects is a byproduct of increased intelligence, specifically selected for only in a few advanced primates, notably the chimpanzee.The adaptiveness of play in pongid (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • On the what_ and _how of learning.R. C. Gonzalez & Matthew Yarczower - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):145-145.
  • Contrasting approaches to a theory of learning.Timothy D. Johnston - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):125-139.
    The general process view of learning, which guided research into learning for the first half of this century, has come under attack in recent years from several quarters. One form of criticism has come from proponents of the so-called biological boundaries approach to learning. These theorists have presented a variety of data showing that supposedly general laws of learning may in fact be limited in their applicability to different species and learning tasks, and they argue that the limitations are drawn (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   287 citations  
  • Systematicity and the Continuity Thesis.K. Brad Wray - 2019 - Synthese 196 (3):819-832.
    Hoyningen-Huene develops an account of what science is, distinguishing it from common sense. According to Hoyningen-Huene, the key distinguishing feature is that science is more systematic. He identifies nine ways in which science is more systematic than common sense. I compare Hoyningen-Huene’s view to a view I refer to as the “Continuity Thesis.” The Continuity Thesis states that scientific knowledge is just an extension of common sense. This thesis is associated with Quine, Planck, and others. I argue that Hoyningen-Huene ultimately (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The facts about fantasy.Dennis P. Wolf - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):172-172.
  • The evolution of intelligence: rehabilitation of recapitulation?Jan Wind - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):398-399.
  • Possible Persons and the Problem of Prenatal Harm.Nicola Jane Williams - 2013 - The Journal of Ethics 17 (4):355-385.
    When attempting to determine which of our acts affect future generations and which affect the identities of those who make up such generations, accounts of personal identity that privilege psychological features and person affecting accounts of morality, whilst highly useful when discussing the rights and wrongs of acts relating to extant persons, seem to come up short. On such approaches it is often held that the intuition that future persons can be harmed by decisions made prior to their existence is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • In defense of exaptation.Wendy Wilkins & Jennie Dumford - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):763-764.
  • Mutationism, not Lamarckism, captures the novelty of CRISPR–Cas.Jeremy G. Wideman, S. Andrew Inkpen, W. Ford Doolittle & Rosemary J. Redfield - 2019 - Biology and Philosophy 34 (1):12.
    Koonin, in an article in this issue, claims that CRISPR–Cas systems are mechanisms for the inheritance of acquired adaptive characteristics, and that the operation of such systems comprises a “Lamarckian mode of evolution.” We argue that viewing the CRISPR–Cas mechanism as facilitating a form of “directed mutation” more accurately represents how the system behaves and the history of neoDarwinian thinking, and is to be preferred.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Missing variables in studies of animal learning.Wally Welker - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):161-161.
  • Astrophysical fine tuning, naturalism, and the contemporary design argument.Mark A. Walker & M. Milan - 2006 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 20 (3):285 – 307.
    Evidence for instances of astrophysical 'fine tuning' (or 'coincidences') is thought by some to lend support to the design argument (i.e. the argument that our universe has been designed by some deity). We assess some of the relevant empirical and conceptual issues. We argue that astrophysical fine tuning calls for some explanation, but this explanation need not appeal to the design argument. A clear and strict separation of the issue of anthropic fine tuning on one hand and any form of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Astrophysical Fine Tuning, Naturalism, and the Contemporary Design Argument.Mark A. Walker & Milan M. Ćirković - 2006 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 20 (3):285-307.
    Evidence for instances of astrophysical ‘fine tuning’ (or ‘coincidences’) is thought by some to lend support to the design argument (i.e. the argument that our universe has been designed by some deity). We assess some of the relevant empirical and conceptual issues. We argue that astrophysical fine tuning calls for some explanation, but this explanation need not appeal to the design argument. A clear and strict separation of the issue of anthropic fine tuning on one hand and any form of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The essentials of play?Brian Vandenberg - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):171-172.
  • Why chimps matter to language origin.Ib Ulbaek - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):762-763.
  • Toward an adaptationist psycholinguistics.John Tooby & Leda Cosmides - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):760-762.
  • Grammar yes, generative grammar no.Michael Tomasello - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):759-760.
  • The epistemology of the play theorist.Brian Sutton-Smith - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):170-171.
  • Why does play matter?Stephen J. Suomi - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):169-170.
  • The view of language.Michael Studdert-Kennedy - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):758-759.
  • The evolution of theoretically useful traits.Rowland Stout - 1998 - Biology and Philosophy 13 (4):529-540.
    The purely theoretical notion of fitness or optimality that is employed for instance in optimization theory has come under attack from those who think that only a more historically based notion of fitness could have a central role in evolutionary explanation. They argue that the key notion is proven usefulness rather than theoretical usefulness. This paper articulates a notion of theoretical usefulness and defends its role in functional evolutionary explanations.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The evolution of the language faculty: A paradox and its solution.Dan Sperber - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-758.
  • Anatomizing the rhinoceros.Elliott Sober - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):764-765.
  • Ontogeny does not always recapitulate phylogeny.Charles T. Snowdon & Jeffrey A. French - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):397-398.
  • The current state of play.Peter K. Smith - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):172-184.
  • An alternative model for language acquisition.Euclid O. Smith - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):397-397.
  • An ecological theory of learning: Good goal, poor strategy.Sara J. Shettleworth - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):160-161.
  • A Defense of Integrity as a Conservation Concept.J. Michael Scoville - 2016 - Ethics and the Environment 21 (2):79-117.
    An environmental ethic needs to have an answer to two basic questions: what nature should we care about, and why? A number of proposals have been made about how to answer these questions. In this paper, I consider in detail one such proposal, namely, biological or ecological integrity. Different characterizations of integrity can be found in the literature, but I will treat the following one as paradigmatic. Integrity refers to a property of landscapes that are relatively unmodified by human activity (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The ecology of learning: The right answer to the wrong question.Barry Schwartz - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):159-160.
  • Play as a mode.Helen B. Schwartzman - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):168-169.
  • Moving Ourselves, Moving Others: Motion and Emotion in Intersubjectivity, Consciousness, and Language.Andrea Schiavio - 2015 - Philosophical Psychology 28 (5):735-739.
  • Adaptive modification of behavior: Processing information from the environment.Wolfgang M. Schleidt - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):158-159.
  • Chimpanzees and protolanguage.Sue Savage-Rumbaugh, Duane M. Rumbaugh & Sally Boysen - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):396-397.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explaining diversity and searching for general processes: Isn't there a middle ground?Paul Rozin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):157-158.
  • Arbitrariness no argument against adaption.Mark Ridley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-756.
  • In Defence of Selfish Genes.Richard Dawkins - 1981 - Philosophy 56 (218):556.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Known general principles of learning cannot be ignored.Sam Revusky - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):156-157.
  • Learning theory in its niche.Howard Rachlin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):155-156.
  • Affordances and Phenomenal Character in Spatial Perception.Simon Prosser - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (4):475-513.
    Intentionalism is the view that the phenomenal character of a conscious experience is wholly determined by, or even reducible to, its representational content. In this essay I put forward a version of intentionalism that allows (though does not require) the reduction of phenomenal character to representational content. Unlike other reductionist theories, however, it does not require the acceptance of phenomenal externalism (the view that phenomenal character does not supervene on the internal state of the subject). According the view offered here, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • On the coevolution of language and social competence.David Premack - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):754-756.
  • Play—immediate or long-term adaptiveness?Frank E. Poirier - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):167-168.
  • Adaptive Skeletal Muscle Action Requires Anticipation and “Conscious Broadcasting”.T. Andrew Poehlman, Tiffany K. Jantz & Ezequiel Morsella - 2012 - Frontiers in Psychology 3.
  • Is an ecological approach radical enough?H. C. Plotkin & F. J. Odling-Smee - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):154-155.
  • Natural language and natural selection.Steven Pinker & Paul Bloom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):707-27.
    Many people have argued that the evolution of the human language faculty cannot be explained by Darwinian natural selection. Chomsky and Gould have suggested that language may have evolved as the by-product of selection for other abilities or as a consequence of as-yet unknown laws of growth and form. Others have argued that a biological specialization for grammar is incompatible with every tenet of Darwinian theory – that it shows no genetic variation, could not exist in any intermediate forms, confers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   598 citations  
  • Issues in the evolution of the human language faculty.Steven Pinker & Paul Bloom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):765-784.