Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Reformulating Mill’s Harm Principle.Ben Saunders - 2016 - Mind 125 (500):1005-1032.
    Mill’s harm principle is commonly supposed to rest on a distinction between self-regarding conduct, which is not liable to interference, and other-regarding conduct, which is. As critics have noted, this distinction is difficult to draw. Furthermore, some of Mill’s own applications of the principle, such as his forbidding of slavery contracts, do not appear to fit with it. This article proposes that the self-regarding/other-regarding distinction is not in fact fundamental to Mill’s harm principle. The sphere of protected liberty includes not (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Response to Open Peer Commentaries on “Trans Fat Bans and Human Freedom”.David Resnik - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (3):4-5.
    A growing body of evidence has linked consumption of trans fatty acids to cardiovascular disease. To promote public health, numerous state and local governments in the United States have banned the use of artificial trans fats in restaurant foods, and additional bans may follow. Although these policies may have a positive impact on human health, they open the door to excessive government control over food, which could restrict dietary choices, interfere with cultural, ethnic, and religious traditions, and exacerbate socioeconomic inequalities. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What’s Wrong with Mandatory Nutrient Limits? Rethinking Dietary Freedom, Free Markets and Food Reformulation.Jenny Claire Kaldor - 2018 - Public Health Ethics 11 (1):54-68.
    Around the world, unhealthy diets are a leading cause of disease. Shifting population diets in a healthier direction will require downstream policy interventions. This means changing the composition of the processed food supply, particularly reducing salt, sugar and fat. Mandatory nutrient limits imposed by government are one way of achieving this. However, they have been criticized as a particularly intrusive regulatory option, interfering with both free markets and free choices. At the same time, voluntary industry reformulation has become an intervention (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bloomberg's Health Legacy: Urban Innovator or Meddling Nanny?Lawrence O. Gostin - 2013 - Hastings Center Report 43 (5):19-25.
    Michael Bloomberg assumed office as the 108th mayor of New York City on January 1, 2002. As he leaves the mayoralty—having won re—election twice‐his public health legacy is bitterly contested. The public health community views him as an urban innovator—a rare political and business leader willing to fight for a built environment conducive to healthier, safer lifestyles. To his detractors, Bloomberg epitomizes a meddling nanny—an elitist dictating to largely poor and working—class people about how they ought to lead their lives. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Equity and preventive regulations.Elizabeth Fenton - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (5):329-330.
    In ‘Obesity, equity and choice’, Timothy Wilkinson argues that preventive regulations to address obesity, such as taxes on sugary drinks, are at worst inequitable and at best fail to increase or improve equity. He concludes that we do not yet have good reasons to adopt them. I argue that equity considerations are not as problematic for preventive regulations as Wilkinson suggests.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation