Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Culture and Cognition: What is Universal about the Representation of Color Experience?Kimberly Jameson - 2005 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 5 (3-4):293-348.
    Existing research in color naming and categorization primarily reflects two opposing views: A Cultural Relativist view that posits color perception is greatly shaped by culturally specific language associations and perceptual learning, and a Universalist view that emphasizes panhuman shared color processing as the basis for color naming similarities within and across cultures. Recent empirical evidence finds color processing differs both within and across cultures. This divergent color processing raises new questions about the sources of previously observed cultural coherence and cross-cultural (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • ""What Does" Society" Look Like?Linnda R. Caporael - 2008 - Biological Theory 3 (2):103-107.
  • Human and nonhuman systems are adaptive in a different sense.Tamás Zétényi - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):507-508.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defense of exaptation.Wendy Wilkins & Jennie Dumford - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):763-764.
  • Conventional Wisdom: Negotiating Conventions of Reference Enhances Category Learning.John Voiklis & James E. Corter - 2012 - Cognitive Science 36 (4):607-634.
    Collaborators generally coordinate their activities through communication, during which they readily negotiate a shared lexicon for activity-related objects. This social-pragmatic activity both recruits and affects cognitive and social-cognitive processes ranging from selective attention to perspective taking. We ask whether negotiating reference also facilitates category learning or might private verbalization yield comparable facilitation? Participants in three referential conditions learned to classify imaginary creatures according to combinations of functional features—nutritive and destructive—that implicitly defined four categories. Remote partners communicated in the Dialogue condition. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why chimps matter to language origin.Ib Ulbaek - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):762-763.
  • Computational resources do constrain behavior.John K. Tsotsos - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):506-507.
  • Toward an adaptationist psycholinguistics.John Tooby & Leda Cosmides - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):760-762.
  • Grammar yes, generative grammar no.Michael Tomasello - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):759-760.
  • The view of language.Michael Studdert-Kennedy - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):758-759.
  • The evolution of the language faculty: A paradox and its solution.Dan Sperber - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-758.
  • Anatomizing the rhinoceros.Elliott Sober - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):764-765.
  • Rationality and irrationality: Still fighting words.Paul Snow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):505-506.
  • A Bayesian theory of thought.Howard Smokler - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):505-505.
  • But how does the brain think?Steven L. Small - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):504-505.
  • The rationality of causal inference.Thomas R. Shultz - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):503-504.
  • On the nonapplicability of a rational analysis to human cognition.Eldar Shafir - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):502-503.
  • Rational analysis will not throw off the yoke of the precision-importance trade-off function.Wolfgang Schwarz - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):501-502.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Justification, sociality, and autonomy.Frederick F. Schmitt - 1987 - Synthese 73 (1):43 - 85.
    Theories of epistemically justified belief have long assumed individualism. In its extreme, or Lockean, form individualism rules out justified belief on testimony by insisting that a subject is justified in believing a proposition only if he or she possesses first-hand justification for it. The skeptical consequences of extreme individualism have led many to adopt a milder version, attributable to Hume, on which a subject is justified in believing a proposition only if he or she is justified in believing that there (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Arbitrariness no argument against adaption.Mark Ridley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-756.
  • Making good psychology out of blending theory.Raymond W. Gibbs Jr - 2001 - Cognitive Linguistics 11 (3-4):347-358.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The cognitive laboratory, the library and the Skinner box.Howard Rachlin - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):501-501.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the coevolution of language and social competence.David Premack - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):754-756.
  • Natural language and natural selection.Steven Pinker & Paul Bloom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):707-27.
    Many people have argued that the evolution of the human language faculty cannot be explained by Darwinian natural selection. Chomsky and Gould have suggested that language may have evolved as the by-product of selection for other abilities or as a consequence of as-yet unknown laws of growth and form. Others have argued that a biological specialization for grammar is incompatible with every tenet of Darwinian theory – that it shows no genetic variation, could not exist in any intermediate forms, confers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   598 citations  
  • Issues in the evolution of the human language faculty.Steven Pinker & Paul Bloom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):765-784.
  • An ideological battle over modals and quantifiers.Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):752-754.
  • Complexity and adaptation.David Pesetsky & Ned Block - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):750-752.
  • The emergence of homo loquens and the laws of physics.Carlos P. Otero - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):747-750.
  • The genome might as well store the entire language in the environment.Anat Ninio - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):746-747.
  • Natural selection and the autonomy of syntax.Frederick J. Newmeyer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):745-746.
  • Spatial language and spatial representation: a cross-linguistic comparison.Edward Munnich, Barbara Landau & Barbara Anne Dosher - 2001 - Cognition 81 (3):171-208.
  • Self‐Repair Increases Referential Coordination.Gregory Mills & Gisela Redeker - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (8):e13329.
    When interlocutors repeatedly describe referents to each other, they rapidly converge on referring expressions which become increasingly systematized and abstract as the interaction progresses. Previous experimental research suggests that interactive repair mechanisms in dialogue underpin convergence. However, this research has so far only focused on the role of other-initiated repair and has not examined whether self-initiated repair might also play a role. To investigate this question, we report the results from a computer-mediated maze task experiment. In this task, participants communicate (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Growth points from the very beginning.David McNeill, Susan Duncan, Jonathan Cole, Shaun Gallagher & Bennett Bertenthal - 2010 - In M. Arbib D. Bickerton (ed.), The Emergence of Protolanguage: Holophrasis Vs Compositionality. John Benjamins. pp. 117-132.
    Did protolanguage users use discrete words that referred to objects, actions, locations, etc., and then, at some point, combine them; or on the contrary did they have words that globally indexed whole semantic complexes, and then come to divide them? Our answer is: early humans were forming language units consisting of global and discrete dimensions of semiosis in dynamic opposition. These units of thinking-for-speaking, or ‘growth points’ (GPs) were, jointly, analog imagery (visuo-spatio-motoric) and categorically-contrastive (-emic) linguistic encodings. This discrete-global duality (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Adaptive rationality and identifiability of psychological processes.Dominic W. Massaro & Daniel Friedman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):499-501.
  • Middle position on language, cognition, and evolution.Michael Maratsos - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):744-745.
  • Causal stories.David Magnus - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):744-744.
  • Adaptive complexity in sound patterns.Björn Lindblom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):743-744.
  • Language evolved – So what's new?John Limber - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):742-743.
  • Not invented here.Philip Lieberman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):741-742.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How much did the brain have to change for speech?R. C. Lewontin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):740-741.
  • The social life of cognition.Joanna Korman, John Voiklis & Bertram F. Malle - 2015 - Cognition 135:30-35.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Lessons from the study of speech perception.Keith R. Kluender - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):739-740.
  • Five exaptations in speech: Reducing the arbitrariness of the constraints on language.John Kingston - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):738-739.
  • What would a theory of language evolution have to look like?Ray Jackendoff - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):737-738.
  • Beyond the roadblock in linguistic evolution studies.James R. Hurford - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):736-737.
  • The Importance of a Consideration of Qualia to Imagery and Cognition.Timothy L. Hubbard - 1995 - Consciousness and Cognition 5 (3):327-358.
    Experiences of qualia, subjective sensory-like aspects of stimuli, are central to imagistic representation. Following Raffman , qualia are considered to reflect experiential knowledge distinct from descriptive, abstract, and propositional knowledge; following Jackendoff , objective neural activity is distinguished from subjective experience. It is argued that descriptive physical knowledge does not provide an adequate accounting of qualia, and philosophical scenarios such as the Turing test and the Chinese Room are adapted to demonstrate inadequacies of accounts of cognition that ignore subjective experience. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Selecting grammars.Norbert Hornstein - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):735-736.
  • Probing the “Achilles' heel” of rational analysis.Keith J. Holyoak - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):498-499.
  • Spatial language and spatial representation.William G. Hayward & Michael J. Tarr - 1995 - Cognition 55 (1):39-84.
  • Rational analysis and the Lens model.Reid Hastie & Kenneth R. Hammond - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):498-498.