Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Mathematical models and reality: A constructivist perspective. [REVIEW]Christian Hennig - 2010 - Foundations of Science 15 (1):29-48.
    To explore the relation between mathematical models and reality, four different domains of reality are distinguished: observer-independent reality, personal reality, social reality and mathematical/formal reality. The concepts of personal and social reality are strongly inspired by constructivist ideas. Mathematical reality is social as well, but constructed as an autonomous system in order to make absolute agreement possible. The essential problem of mathematical modelling is that within mathematics there is agreement about ‘truth’, but the assignment of mathematics to informal reality is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The maladies of enlightenment science.Tim Wyatt - 2017 - Ethics in Science and Environmental Politics 17 (1):51-62.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theories of rationality and principles of charity.Robert Wachbroit - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (1):35-47.
  • Editorial introduction: Philipp Frank, a physicist-turned-philosopher.Adam Tamas Tuboly - 2017 - Studies in East European Thought 69 (3):199-206.
  • Social functionalist frameworks for judgment and choice: Intuitive politicians, theologians, and prosecutors.Philip E. Tetlock - 2002 - Psychological Review 109 (3):451-471.
  • A Tale of Three Theories: Feyerabend and Popper on Progress and the Aim of Science.Luca Tambolo - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 51:33-41.
    In this paper, three theories of progress and the aim of science are discussed: the theory of progress as increasing explanatory power, advocated by Popper in The logic of scientific discovery ; the theory of progress as approximation to the truth, introduced by Popper in Conjectures and refutations ; the theory of progress as a steady increase of competing alternatives, which Feyerabend put forward in the essay “Reply to criticism. Comments on Smart, Sellars and Putnam” and defended as late as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The diversity of modes of discourse and the development of sociological knowledge.Nico Stehr & Anthony Simmons - 1979 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 10 (1):141-161.
    This paper presents an analysis of the structure of contemporary sociological knowledge in terms of a theory of scientific discourse. The concept of 'discourse' is introduced as a theoretical refinement of the concept of 'paradigm' and is applied to the classes of knowledge claims of the natural and social sciences. It is concluded that general modes of scientific discourse are definable in terms of their vertical differentiation from everyday discourse, while particular modes of sociological discourse are additionally definable in terms (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A case for the 'middle ground': exploring the tensions of postmodern thought in nursing.Kelli I. Stajduhar, Lynda Balneaves & Sally E. Thorne - 2001 - Nursing Philosophy 2 (1):72-82.
    Diverse beliefs about the nature and essence of scientific truth are pervasive in the nursing literature. Most recently, rejection of a more traditional and objective truth has resulted in a shift toward an emphasis on the acceptance of multiple and subjective truths. Some nursing scholars have discarded the idea that objective truth exists at all, but instead have argued that subjective truth is the only knowable truth and therefore the one that ought to govern nursing's disciplinary inquiry. Yet, there has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reviews : Gerd Gigerenzer, Zeno Swijtink, Theodore Porter, Lorraine Daston, John Beatty and Lorenz Kruger, The Empire of Chance: How Probability Changed Science and Everyday Life, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989, £30.00, xvii + 340 pp. [REVIEW]Vito Signorile - 1990 - History of the Human Sciences 3 (2):279-286.
  • Theory choice in a two-level science.Geoffrey Sampson - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (4):303-318.
  • How we load our data sets with theories and why we do so purposefully.Guillaume Rochefort-Maranda - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 60:1-6.
    In this paper, I compare theory-laden perceptions with imputed data sets. The similarities between the two allow me to show how the phenomenon of theory-ladenness can manifest itself in statistical analyses. More importantly, elucidating the differences between them will allow me to broaden the focus of the existing literature on theory-ladenness and to introduce some much-needed nuances.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reviews. [REVIEW]Jerome R. Ravetz - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (2):265-268.
  • The rise of Western rationalism: Paul Feyerabend’s story.John Preston - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:79-86.
    I summarise certain aspects of Paul Feyerabend’s account of the development of Western rationalism, show the ways in which that account is supposed to run up against an alternative, that of Karl Popper, and then try to give a preliminary comparison of the two. My interest is primarily in whether what Feyerabend called his ‘story’ constitutes a possible history of our epistemic concepts and their trajectory. I express some grave reservations about that story, and about Feyerabend’s framework, finding Popper’s views (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Pluralism and naturalism: Why the proliferation of theories is good for the mind.Christopher J. Preston - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (6):715 – 735.
    A number of those that have advocated for theoretical pluralism in epistemology suggest that naturalistic arguments from cognitive science can support their case. Yet these theorists have traditionally faced two pressing needs. First, they have needed a cognitive science adequate to the task. Second, they have needed a bridge between whatever scientific account of cognition they favor and the normative claims of a pluralistic epistemology. Both of these challenges are addressed below in an argument for theoretical pluralism that brings together (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Epistemological Engine.Joseph Pitt - 1983 - Philosophica 32.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Understanding Ethics in Practice.Nelson Phillips - 1992 - Business Ethics Quarterly 2 (2):223-244.
    Business ethics is an eclectic blend of intellectual traditions that seeks to examine the question of "what should I do in my businessrelationships." This paper attempts to widen this discussion by proposing an alternative view of the nature of ethical behaviour: ethical behaviour as a situated social accomplishment. From an ethnomethodological perspective, norms and rules have the status of interpretive aids whieh are used to negotiate an acceptable meaning for a situation; norms and rules are constituted by, and in part (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Understanding Ethics in Practice.Nelson Phillips - 1992 - Business Ethics Quarterly 2 (2):223-244.
    Business ethics is an eclectic blend of intellectual traditions that seeks to examine the question of "what should I do in my businessrelationships." This paper attempts to widen this discussion by proposing an alternative view of the nature of ethical behaviour: ethical behaviour as a situated social accomplishment. From an ethnomethodological perspective, norms and rules have the status of interpretive aids whieh are used to negotiate an acceptable meaning for a situation; norms and rules are constituted by, and in part (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Against a Universal Definition of 'Type'.Tomas Petricek - unknown
    What is the definition of 'type'? Having a clear and precise answer to this question would avoid many misunderstandings and prevent meaningless discussions that arise from them. But having such clear and precise answer to this question would also hurt science, "hamper the growth of knowledge" and "deflect the course of investigation into narrow channels of things already understood". In this essay, I argue that not everything we work with needs to be precisely defined. There are many definitions used by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The discovery/justification context dichotomy within formal and computational models of scientific theories: a weakening of the distinction based on the perspective of non-monotonic logics.Jorge A. Morales & Mauricio Molina Delgado - 2016 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 26 (4):315-335.
    The present paper analyses the topic of scientific discovery and the problem of the existence of a logical framework involved in such endeavour. We inquire how several non-monotonic logic frameworks and other formalisms can account for such a task. In the same vein, we analyse some key aspects of the historical and theoretical debate surrounding scientific discovery, in particular, the context of discovery and context of justification context distinction. We present an argument concerning the weakening of the discovery/justification context dichotomy (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Induction and scientific realism: Einstein versus Van Fraassen part three: Einstein, aim-oriented empiricism and the discovery of special and general relativity.Nicholas Maxwell - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):275-305.
    In this paper I show that Einstein made essential use of aim-oriented empiricism in scientific practice in developing special and general relativity. I conclude by considering to what extent Einstein came explicitly to advocate aim-oriented empiricism in his later years.
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Universities as Social Background in “Trading Zone” Creation.Evgeny Maslanov - 2019 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 49 (6):493-509.
    The article analyzes the conception of a trading zone as a space of action and belief coordination. P. Galison proposed the conception based on anthropological and linguistic analogies. The article reviews the anthropological analogies aimed at building up the conception and the legitimacy of their use. The conclusion is that the analogies used are not accurate enough. If the tribes interacting in trading zones have a common history, material culture, and practices, they can hardly have significant differences. If they are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “The Battle is on”: Lakatos, Feyerabend, and the student protests.Eric C. Martin - 2019 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 9 (2):1-33.
    This paper shows how late 1960’s student protests influenced the thought of Imre Lakatos and Paul Feyerabend. I argue that student movements shaped their work from this period, specifically Lakatos’s “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes” and Feyerabend’s Against Method. Archival evidence shows that their political environments at London and Berkeley inflected their writing on scientific method, entrenching Lakatos’s search for a rationalist account of scientific development, and encouraging Feyerabend’s ‘anarchistic’ theory of knowledge. I document this influence and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Null hypothesis testing ≠ Scientific inference: A critique of the shaky premise at the heart of the science and values debate, and a defense of value‐neutral risk assessment.Brian H. MacGillivray - forthcoming - Risk Analysis.
    Many philosophers and statisticians argue that risk assessors are morally obligated to evaluate the probabilities and consequences of methodological error, and to base their decisions of whether to adopt a given parameter value, model, or hypothesis on those considerations. This argument is couched within the rubric of null hypothesis testing, which I suggest is a poor descriptive and normative model for risk assessment. Risk regulation is not primarily concerned with evaluating the probability of data conditional upon the null hypothesis, but (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evers & Walker and forms of knowledge.Jim Mackenzie - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 19 (2):199–209.
    Jim Mackenzie; Evers & Walker and Forms of Knowledge, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 19, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 199–209, https://doi.org/10.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Evers & Walker and Forms of Knowledge.Jim Mackenzie - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 19 (2):199-209.
    Jim Mackenzie; Evers & Walker and Forms of Knowledge, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 19, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 199–209, https://doi.org/10.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reviews. [REVIEW]Scott A. Kleiner - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (2):261-265.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genes.Philip Kitcher - 1982 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33 (4):337-359.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Historical Contingency and the Impact of Scientific Imperialism.Ian James Kidd - 2013 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 27 (3):317–326.
    In a recent article in this journal, Steve Clarke and Adrian Walsh propose a normative basis for John Dupré’s criticisms of scientific imperialism, namely, that scientific imperialism can cause a discipline to fail to progress in ways that it otherwise would have. This proposal is based on two presuppositions: one, that scientific disciplines have developmental teleologies, and two, that these teleologies are optimal. I argue that we should reject both of these presuppositions and so conclude that Clarke and Walsh’s proposal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Gift versus Trade: On the Culture of Science Communication.Ilya Kasavin - 2019 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 49 (6):453-472.
    This article aims at a critical reevaluation of the trading zone concept. It starts from a case study of the Faraday–Whewell collaboration in coming to terms with electrolysis experiments. The case is supposed to be an example of a trade zone of science/philosophy interaction though it demonstrates the unequal nature of the “trade.” This requires the analysis to log in some details concerning Galison’s metaphor of trading zones, which reveals its market-oriented connotations. The following criticism of the market metaphor for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Physical Laws, Physical Entities and Ontology.E. Kaeser - 1977 - Dialectica 31 (3‐4):273-299.
    We investigate the way physical laws objectively refer to the entities they are about. Laws of mathematical physics do not refer directly to the “real world” but to an ideal specific domain of objects, which we term “scope”. In order to find out which real objects physical laws deal with, reference to the scope is not sufficient. We need in addition the search for domains to which laws apply — i. e. “empirical domains”— in order to establish their reference to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popular Culture and the Dilemma of Corruption in Nigeria.Adekunle A. Ibrahim & Samuel Otu Ishaya - 2018 - Human and Social Studies 7 (3):47-65.
    This paper examines the nexus between popular culture and the problem of corruption in Nigeria within the theoretical framework of the Socratic dictum that “the unexamined life is not worth living”. The paper argues that corruption is a social behavior that is propelled by popular culture and sustained by skewed application of logical thinking in critical decision making. Hence, the paper posits that formal education remains the bedrock upon which corruption can be curtailed and also equips people with logical tools (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evaluating Complementary and Alternative Medicine: The Limits of Science and of Scientists.David J. Hufford - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (2):198-212.
    Science provides the most important set of tools for the evaluation of complementary and alternative medicine. Nonetheless, there are important limits in science that constrain its ability to evaluate CAM effectively. Some are the limits encountered by science in conventional medical research. Others are peculiar to this controversial topic. The most important limits are not those inherent within the basic methods of science, but rather within the culture of science — the particular ways that scientific knowledge, theory, and method are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Comparing the long-term evolution of ``cognitive invariances'' in physics with a dynamics in states of consciousness.Gerhard Grössing - 2001 - Foundations of Science 6 (4):255-272.
    It is shown that the evolution of physics canin several regards be described by elements of``regression'', i.e., that within a certaintradition of ideas one begins with theconstruction of most ``plausible'' statements(axioms) at hand, and then ``works onselfbackwards'' with respect to developmental terms.As a consequence of this strategy, the furtherwork proceeds along such a ``regressive'' path,the more one arrives at concepts andrelationships which are unexpected or evencounter-intuitive in terms of our everydayexperiences. However, a comparable phenomenology is wellknown from studies on states (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Between rationalism and relativism. On Larry Laudan's model of scientific rationality.Adam Grobler - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (4):493-507.
    In the early sixties there broke out a fierce controversy concerning rationality in science which was labelled as the Popper-Kuhn controversy. It can be conceived in terms of the rationalism-relativism opposition. This may seem dubious, for the proper contrast to rationalism is irrationalism, and the one to relativism is absolutism. What is at issue, however, is whether scientific change comes about in consequence of argument or in consequence of-to use Kuhn's favourite dictum-conversion. The notion of argument does not involve here (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Book Reviews. [REVIEW]Diane Greco, Lesley B. Cormack, Robert J. O'Hara, Katherine Hawley & Ioannis Votsis - 2007 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21 (1):103-117.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A normative theory of humanistic knowledge.Frans Gregersen & Simo Køppe - 1989 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 20 (1):40-53.
    Ausgehend von der Gegenüberstellung der Wissenschaftlichkeit der Naturwissenschaften und der Geisteswissenschaften wird argumentiert, daß Wissenschaftlichkeit nur auf der Basis einer Zusammenstellung wissenschaftstheoretischer, wissenschaftsgeschichtlicher und wissenschaftssoziologischer Kriterien definiert werden kann. Eine solche dreiteilige Definition wird skizziert, und es wird behauptet, daß dies gültig sowohl für die Naturwissenschaften als auch für die Geisteswissenschaften ist. Es folgt daraus, daß es im Prinzip keine Verschiedenheit zwischen der Wissenschaftlichkeit der einen Basiswissenschaft und der anderen gibt. Die Formulierung dreier normativer Kriterien für Wissenschaft als solche schließt (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • ¿Qué entiende Feyerabend por Metafísica?María Teresa Gargiulo - 2015 - Agora 34 (1).
    Feyerabend a lo largo de su obra varía y reforma el abordaje de la cuestión acerca de la relación entre ciencia y metafísica. Sus especialistas conocen con frecuencia cómo plantea dicha cuestión entre los 60 y finales de los 70, cuando está preocupado por resolver el problema de la inconmensurabilidad. Pero desconocen su posterior evolución. El objetivo de esta comunicación es presentar, a través de las confrontaciones que Feyerabend mantiene con sus interlocutores, las distintas connotaciones y roles que adquiere la (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paul Karl Feyerabend Las proyecciones de la proliferación teórica en la relación ciencia-metafísica.María Teresa Gargiulo de Vázquez - 2015 - Anales Del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 32 (1).
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La doctrina de la inconmensurabilidad en Paul Feyerabend: una objeción contra una particular concepción de racionalidad científica.Teresa Gargiulo - 2017 - Pensamiento 73 (276):335-362.
    La inconmensurabilidad ha ocasionado innumerables controversias y debates. En estos parece ser unánime la interpretación de tal doctrina como una objeción contra la objetividad, el realismo y el progreso científico. Ahora bien, este marco hermenéutico es estrecho para poder comprender la intencionalidad de Paul Feyerabend al formular su doctrina de la inconmensurabilidad. Pues éste no pretendió cuestionar nunca a dichas nociones en cuanto tales sino únicamente mostrar cuán vano resulta ser el intento del neo-positivismo y del racionalismo popperiano por definirlas. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Feyerabend ¿un filósofo de la ciencia posmoderno?Teresa Gargiulo - 2017 - Anales Del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 34 (1):203-227.
    El pensamiento de Feyerabend ha sido objeto de múltiples y divergentes interpretaciones. Pero entre ellas parece ser unánime la inscripción de su obra dentro de las coordenadas de una epistemología posmoderna. Estas lecturas podrían encontrar sustento en su anarquismo epistemológico el cual constituye en sí mismo una reducción al absurdo de los intentos del positivismo lógico y del racionalismo crítico por definir axiomática o metodológicamente la ciencia. En este sentido, su obra puede ser entendida, en parte, como una argumentación negativa (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • El realismo normativo de Paul Karl Feyerabend y su defensa de la metafísica.María Teresa Gargiulo - 2015 - Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad Del Norte 23:182-212.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Critical Notice of T he Case of the Female Orgasm: Bias in the Science of Evolution. [REVIEW]Lisa Gannett - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (4):619-638.
  • The Case of the Female Orgasm. [REVIEW]Lisa Gannett - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (4):619-638.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a Refined Depiction of Nature of Science.Igal Galili - 2019 - Science & Education 28 (3-5):503-537.
    This study considers the short list of Nature of Science features frequently published and widely known in the science education discourse. It is argued that these features were oversimplified and a refinement of the claims may enrich or sometimes reverse them. The analysis shows the need to address the range of variation in each particular aspect of NOS and to illustrate these variations with actual events from the history of science in order to adequately present the subject. Another implication of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Galilean Approach to the Galileo Affair, 1609–2009.Maurice A. Finocchiaro - 2011 - Science & Education 20 (1):51-66.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Changing patterns of reconstruction.Paul Feyerabend - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (4):351-369.
  • Life Stories: Beyond Construction.Ann Eide - 2012 - Journal of Critical Realism 11 (2):139-162.
    This article explores the way in which certain theoretical frameworks and analytical procedures combine to present stories about experience as objects of no depth, confusing this artefact with the phenomenon studied. By pointing out abusive potentials in a constructivist approach, it is argued that critical realism is needed in the field of narrative analysis. The creation of life stories as well as the project of analysing them involve interaction with a material world, and elaboration on it. We meet the Other, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shifting the paradigm of philosophy of science: Philosophy of information and a new renaissance. [REVIEW]Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic - 2003 - Minds and Machines 13 (4):521-536.
    Computing is changing the traditional field of Philosophy of Science in a very profound way. First as a methodological tool, computing makes possible ``experimental Philosophy'' which is able to provide practical tests for different philosophical ideas. At the same time the ideal object of investigation of the Philosophy of Science is changing. For a long period of time the ideal science was Physics (e.g., Popper, Carnap, Kuhn, and Chalmers). Now the focus is shifting to the field of Computing/Informatics. There are (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Troubles with Theoretical Virtues: Resisting Theoretical Utility Arguments in Metaphysics.OtÁvio Bueno & Scott A. Shalkowski - 2020 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 101 (2):456-469.
    In this paper we examine theoretical utility arguments in metaphysics. While philosophers claim a procedural continuity with science when using such arguments, we argue that examining famous instances from the history of science expose their fundamental flaws. We find that arguments from theoretical utility invoke considerations that are not truth conducive and that justifications for claims that a theory possesses theoretical virtues often assume the truth of the theory such virtues are supposed to support. We conclude that theoretical utility arguments (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Explication as a Method of Conceptual Re-engineering.Georg Brun - 2016 - Erkenntnis 81 (6):1211-1241.
    Taking Carnap’s classic exposition as a starting point, this paper develops a pragmatic account of the method of explication, defends it against a range of challenges and proposes a detailed recipe for the practice of explicating. It is then argued that confusions are involved in characterizing explications as definitions, and in advocating precising definitions as an alternative to explications. Explication is better characterized as conceptual re-engineering for theoretical purposes, in contrast to conceptual re-engineering for other purposes and improving exactness for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations