Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Giulio Preti ou le Tournant Pragmatique de la Philosophie.Luca Maria Scarantino - 2011 - Revue de Synthèse 132 (2):233-254.
    Cet article présente les traits essentiels de la pensée de Giulio Preti. Il se focalise sur le primat de l’expérience pragmatique pour historiser les principes formels du savoir. L’historicité des a priori acquiert chez Preti la forme d’une historicité du sens commun, conçu comme vecteur historique des structures conceptuelles qui forment la culture. L’intégration des classiques du pragmatisme aux philosophies critiques et transcendantales européennes engendre un tournant pragmatique de la philosophie d’une grande actualité théorique.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • El problema mente-cuerpo y el materialismo eliminativo.David Villena Saldaña - 2016 - Metanoia 1 (2):19-35.
    This paper is divided into three sections. It aims to give some resources for making possible a straightforward debate on the mind-body problem as well as some serious researches in it. Having these goals into account, the first section offers an introduction to the mind-body problem and the second section explains briefly some of the most influential answers to this problem. The third section is devoted to eliminative materialism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logical content and empirical significance.Ken Gemes - 1998 - In Paul Weingartner, Gerhard Schurz & Georg Dorn (eds.), The Role of Pragmatics in Contemporary Philosophy: Proceedings of the 20th International Wittgenstein Symposium, 10-16 August 1997, Kirchberg am Wechsel (Austria). Verlag Halder-Pichler-Tempsky.
    In this paper I will investigate the possibility of completing a Positivist style account of demarcation. One reason for pursuing this project is that standard criticisms of Positivism do not have the bite against the demarcation project that they are often assumed to have. To argue this will be the burden of the first part of this paper. The other reason is that new research in logic has provided machinery not available to the Positivists; machinery that shows promise for solving (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on Scientific Explanation.Burleigh T. Wilkins - 1970 - Dialogue 9 (3):337-355.
    The problem. The purpose of this paper is to provide a general discussion of Aristotle's views on scientific explanation, by which I mean a discussion of Aristotle's treatment of scientific explanation, its structure and its principles, as distinct from Aristotle's own principles of explanation. By means of this distinction I hope to be excused from a discussion of Aristotle on form and matter, potentiality and actuality, and the four causes, and to avoid so far as possible the controversy among commentators (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Facing being: the significance of Thomist ontological epistemology to realism in post-Kantian philosophy.Callum D. Scott - 2014 - South African Journal of Philosophy 33 (3):347-364.
  • Frege’s bedeutung kaip reikšmė ir kaip nurodymas.Albinas A. Plėšnys & Marius Povilas Šaulauskas - 2017 - Problemos 91:30.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Causalidade e teoria quântica.Patrícia Kauark Leite - 2012 - Scientiae Studia 10 (1):165-177.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • ∈ : Formal concepts in a material world truthmaking and exemplification as types of determination.Philipp Keller - 2007 - Dissertation, University of Geneva
    In the first part ("Determination"), I consider different notions of determination, contrast and compare modal with non-modal accounts and then defend two a-modality theses concerning essence and supervenience. I argue, first, that essence is a a-modal notion, i.e. not usefully analysed in terms of metaphysical modality, and then, contra Kit Fine, that essential properties can be exemplified contingently. I argue, second, that supervenience is also an a-modal notion, and that it should be analysed in terms of constitution relations between properties. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ross’s place in the history of analytic philosophy.David Kaspar - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (4):657-674.
    ABSTRACTWith the recent revival of moral intuitionism, the work of W. D. Ross has grown in stature. But if we look at some recent well-regarded histories, anthologies and companions of analytic philosophy, Ross is noticeably absent. This discrepancy of assessments raises the question of Ross’s place in the history of analytic philosophy. Hans-Johann Glock has recently claimed that Ross is not an analytic philosopher at all, but is instead a ‘traditional philosopher’. In this article, I will identify several undeniable features (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • C. I. Lewis.Susan Haack - 1985 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 19:215-238.
    Lewis, according to Kuklick, was ‘a private person’, of ‘unsparing honesty and … utter dedication to the rational pursuit of truth’. He was, Kuklick continues, ‘equally uncompromising in what he expected of his readers, and as a result wrote for and lectured to a tiny group of scholars’. I hope that—since I occasionally find myself borrowing from him and frequently find myself arguing with him—I may count myself as one of the ‘tiny group of scholars’ for whom Lewis wrote. And (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logical Empiricism, Politics, and Professionalism.Scott Edgar - 2009 - Science & Education 18 (2):177-189.
    This paper considers George A. Reisch’s account of the role of Cold War political forces in shaping the apolitical stance that came to dominate philosophy of science in the late 1940s and 1950s. It argues that at least as early as the 1930s, Logical Empiricists such as Rudolf Carnap already held that philosophy of science could not properly have political aims, and further suggests that political forces alone cannot explain this view’s rise to dominance during the Cold War, since political (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Modality and Anti-Metaphysics.Stephen K. McLeod - 2001 - Aldershot: Ashgate.
    Modality and Anti-Metaphysics critically examines the most prominent approaches to modality among analytic philosophers in the twentieth century, including essentialism. Defending both the project of metaphysics and the essentialist position that metaphysical modality is conceptually and ontologically primitive, Stephen McLeod argues that the logical positivists did not succeed in banishing metaphysical modality from their own theoretical apparatus and he offers an original defence of metaphysics against their advocacy of its elimination. -/- Seeking to assuage the sceptical worries which underlie modal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Content, context and composition.M. Bierwisch - unknown
    In the recent debate on the semantic/pragmatic divide, Herman Cappelen and Ernie Lepore (2005) on the one hand, and Fran¸cois Recanati (2004) on the other, occupy almost diametrically opposed positions as regards the role of semantics for communication, while largely agreeing on important features of pragmatics. According to Cappelen and Lepore (CL), semantic context sensitivity of natural language sentences is restricted to what is determined by a particular minimal set of canonically context sensitive expressions. If you try to go beyond (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century.James R. O'Shea - 2008 - In Dermot Moran (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 204.
    This selective overview of the history of American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century begins with certain enduring themes that were developed by the two main founders of classical American pragmatism, Charles Sanders Peirce (1839--1914) and William James. Against the background of the pervasive influence of Kantian and Hegelian idealism in America in the decades surrounding the turn of the century, pragmatism and related philosophical outlooks emphasizing naturalism and realism were dominant during the first three decades of the century. Beginning in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark