Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Henkin Quantifiers and Complete Problems.Andreas Blass & Yuri Gurevich - 1986 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 32:1--16.
  • Expressing Second-order Sentences in Intuitionistic Dependence Logic.Fan Yang - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (2):323-342.
    Intuitionistic dependence logic was introduced by Abramsky and Väänänen [1] as a variant of dependence logic under a general construction of Hodges’ (trump) team semantics. It was proven that there is a translation from intuitionistic dependence logic sentences into second order logic sentences. In this paper, we prove that the other direction is also true, therefore intuitionistic dependence logic is equivalent to second order logic on the level of sentences.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • X Latin American Symposium on Mathematical Logic.Xavier Caicedo - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):214-237.
  • Dependence of variables construed as an atomic formula.Jouko Väänänen & Wilfrid Hodges - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (6):817-828.
    We define a logic capable of expressing dependence of a variable on designated variables only. Thus has similar goals to the Henkin quantifiers of [4] and the independence friendly logic of [6] that it much resembles. The logic achieves these goals by realizing the desired dependence declarations of variables on the level of atomic formulas. By [3] and [17], ability to limit dependence relations between variables leads to existential second order expressive power. Our avoids some difficulties arising in the original (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Classical Negation and Game-Theoretical Semantics.Tero Tulenheimo - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (4):469-498.
    Typical applications of Hintikka’s game-theoretical semantics give rise to semantic attributes—truth, falsity—expressible in the $\Sigma^{1}_{1}$-fragment of second-order logic. Actually a much more general notion of semantic attribute is motivated by strategic considerations. When identifying such a generalization, the notion of classical negation plays a crucial role. We study two languages, $L_{1}$ and $L_{2}$, in both of which two negation signs are available: $\rightharpoondown $ and $\sim$. The latter is the usual GTS negation which transposes the players’ roles, while the former (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ways of branching quantifers.Gila Sher - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (4):393 - 422.
    Branching quantifiers were first introduced by L. Henkin in his 1959 paper ‘Some Remarks on Infmitely Long Formulas’. By ‘branching quantifiers’ Henkin meant a new, non-linearly structured quantiiier-prefix whose discovery was triggered by the problem of interpreting infinitistic formulas of a certain form} The branching (or partially-ordered) quantifier-prefix is, however, not essentially infinitistic, and the issues it raises have largely been discussed in the literature in the context of finitistic logic, as they will be here. Our discussion transcends, however, the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Dichotomy result for independence-friendly prefixes of generalized quantifiers.Merlijn Sevenster - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (4):1224-1246.
    We study the expressive power of independence-friendly quantifier prefixes composed of universal$\left$, existential$\left$, and majority quantifiers$\left$. We provide four quantifier prefixes that can express NP hard properties and show that all quantifier prefixes capable of expressing NP-hard properties embed at least one of these four quantifier prefixes. As for the quantifier prefixes that do not embed any of these four quantifier prefixes, we show that they are equivalent to a first-order quantifier prefix composed of$\forall x$,$\exists x$, and Mx. In unison, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the logic of informational independence and its applications.Gabriel Sandu - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (1):29 - 60.
    We shall introduce in this paper a language whose formulas will be interpreted by games of imperfect information. Such games will be defined in the same way as the games for first-order formulas except that the players do not have complete information of the earlier course of the game. Some simple logical properties of these games will be stated together with the relation of such games of imperfect information to higher-order logic. Finally, a set of applications will be outlined.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Independendly‐Friendly Logic: Dependence and Independence of Quantifiers in Logic.Gabriel Sandu - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (10):691-711.
    Independence‐Friendly logic introduced by Hintikka and Sandu studies patterns of dependence and independence of quantifiers which exceed those found in ordinary first‐order logic. The present survey focuses on the game‐theoretical interpretation of IF‐logic, including connections to solution concepts in classical game theory, but we shall also present its compositional interpretation together with its connections to notions of dependence and dependence between terms.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • If-logic and truth-definition.Gabriel Sandu - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (2):143-164.
    In this paper we show that first-order languages extended with partially ordered connectives and partially ordered quantifiers define, under a certain interpretation, their own truth-predicate. The interpretation in question is in terms of games of imperfect information. This result is compared with those of Kripke and Feferman.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Faut-il enterrer le principe de compositionnalitè?François Rivenc - 1995 - Dialogue 34 (2):305-.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Existential Graphs: What a Diagrammatic Logic of Cognition Might Look Like.Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2011 - History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (3):265-281.
    This paper examines the contemporary philosophical and cognitive relevance of Charles Peirce's diagrammatic logic of existential graphs (EGs), the ‘moving pictures of thought’. The first part brings to the fore some hitherto unknown details about the reception of EGs in the early 1900s that took place amidst the emergence of modern conceptions of symbolic logic. In the second part, philosophical aspects of EGs and their contributions to contemporary logical theory are pointed out, including the relationship between iconic logic and images, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Hintikka’s Independence-Friendly Logic Meets Nelson’s Realizability.Sergei P. Odintsov, Stanislav O. Speranski & Igor Yu Shevchenko - 2018 - Studia Logica 106 (3):637-670.
    Inspired by Hintikka’s ideas on constructivism, we are going to ‘effectivize’ the game-theoretic semantics for independence-friendly first-order logic, but in a somewhat different way than he did in the monograph ‘The Principles of Mathematics Revisited’. First we show that Nelson’s realizability interpretation—which extends the famous Kleene’s realizability interpretation by adding ‘strong negation’—restricted to the implication-free first-order formulas can be viewed as an effective version of GTS for FOL. Then we propose a realizability interpretation for IF-FOL, inspired by the so-called ‘trump (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Degrees of logics with Henkin quantifiers in poor vocabularies.Marcin Mostowski & Konrad Zdanowski - 2004 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 43 (5):691-702.
    We investigate some logics with Henkin quantifiers. For a given logic L, we consider questions of the form: what is the degree of the set of L–tautologies in a poor vocabulary (monadic or empty)? We prove that the set of tautologies of the logic with all Henkin quantifiers in empty vocabulary L*∅ is of degree 0’. We show that the same holds also for some weaker logics like L ∅(Hω) and L ∅(Eω). We show that each logic of the form (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Independence-friendly cylindric set algebras.Allen Mann - 2009 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 17 (6):719-754.
    Independence-friendly logic is a conservative extension of first-order logic that has the same expressive power as existential second-order logic. We attempt to algebraize IF logic in the same spirit as cylindric algebra. We define independence-friendly cylindric set algebras and investigate to what extent they satisfy the axioms of cylindric algebra. We ask whether the equational theory of IF algebras is finitely axiomatizable, and prove two partial results. First, every IF algebra over a structure is an expansion of a Kleene algebra. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Hintikka and the Functions of Logic.Montgomery Link - 2019 - Logica Universalis 13 (2):203-217.
    Jaakko Hintikka points out the power of Skolem functions to affect both what there is and what we know. There is a tension in his presupposition that these functions actually extend the realm of logic. He claims to have resolved the tension by “reconstructing constructivism” along epistemological lines, instead of by a typical ontological construction; however, after the collapse of the distinction between first and second order, that resolution is not entirely satisfactory. Still, it does throw light on the conceptual (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the semantics of the Henkin quantifier.Michał Krynicki & Alistair H. Lachlan - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (2):184-200.
  • Henkin and function quantifiers.Michael Krynicki & Jouko Väänänen - 1989 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 43 (3):273-292.
  • Decidability problems in languages with Henkin quantifiers.Michał Krynicki & Marcin Mostowski - 1992 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 58 (2):149-172.
    Krynicki, M. and M. Mostowski, Decidability problems in languages with Henkin quantifiers, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 58 149–172.We consider the language L with all Henkin quantifiers Hn defined as follows: Hnx1…xny1…yn φ iff f1…fnx1. ..xn φ, ...,fn). We show that the theory of equality in L is undecidable. The proof of this result goes by interpretation of the word problem for semigroups.Henkin quantifiers are strictly related to the function quantifiers Fn defined as follows: Fnx1…xny1…yn φ iff fx1…xn φ,...,f). (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On definability in dependence logic.Juha Kontinen & Jouko Väänänen - 2009 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18 (3):317-332.
    We study the expressive power of open formulas of dependence logic introduced in Väänänen [Dependence logic (Vol. 70 of London Mathematical Society Student Texts), 2007]. In particular, we answer a question raised by Wilfrid Hodges: how to characterize the sets of teams definable by means of identity only in dependence logic, or equivalently in independence friendly logic.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Complete Logics for Elementary Team Properties.Juha Kontinen & Fan Yang - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-41.
    In this paper, we introduce a logic based on team semantics, called $\mathbf {FOT} $, whose expressive power is elementary, i.e., coincides with first-order logic both on the level of sentences and (possibly open) formulas, and we also show that a sublogic of $\mathbf {FOT} $, called $\mathbf {FOT}^{\downarrow } $, captures exactly downward closed elementary (or first-order) team properties. We axiomatize completely the logic $\mathbf {FOT} $, and also extend the known partial axiomatization of dependence logic to dependence logic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Remark on Negation in Dependence Logic.Juha Kontinen & Jouko Väänänen - 2011 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 52 (1):55-65.
    We show that for any pair $\phi$ and $\psi$ of contradictory formulas of dependence logic there is a formula $\theta$ of the same logic such that $\phi\equiv\theta$ and $\psi\equiv\neg\theta$. This generalizes a result of Burgess.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Hintikka’s Take on the Axiom of Choice and the Constructivist Challenge.Radmila Jovanović - 2013 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 2:135-150.
    In the present paper we confront Martin- Löf’s analysis of the axiom of choice with J. Hintikka’s standing on this axiom. Hintikka claims that his game theoretical semantics for Independence Friendly Logic justifies Zermelo’s axiom of choice in a first-order way perfectly acceptable for the constructivists. In fact, Martin- Löf’s results lead to the following considerations:Hintikka preferred version of the axiom of choice is indeed acceptable for the constructivists and its meaning does not involve higher order logic.However, the version acceptable (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Remark on Henkin Sentences and Their Contraries.John P. Burgess - 2003 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 44 (3):185-188.
    That the result of flipping quantifiers and negating what comes after, applied to branching-quantifier sentences, is not equivalent to the negation of the original has been known for as long as such sentences have been studied. It is here pointed out that this syntactic operation fails in the strongest possible sense to correspond to any operation on classes of models.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Quantifiers vs. Quantification Theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 1973 - Dialectica 27 (3‐4):329-358.
  • Independence-friendly logic and axiomatic set theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126 (1-3):313-333.
    In order to be able to express all possible patterns of dependence and independence between variables, we have to replace the traditional first-order logic by independence-friendly (IF) logic. Our natural concept of truth for a quantificational sentence S says that all the Skolem functions for S exist. This conception of truth for a sufficiently rich IF first-order language can be expressed in the same language. In a first-order axiomatic set theory, one can apparently express this same concept in set-theoretical terms, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Hyperclassical logic (A.K.A. IF logic) and its implications for logical theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):404-423.
    Let us assume that you are entrusted by UNESCO with an important task. You are asked to devise a universal logical language, a Begriffsschrift in Frege's sense, which is to serve the purposes of science, business and everyday life. What requirements should such a “conceptual notation” satisfy? There are undoubtedly many relevant desiderata, but here I am focusing on one unmistakable one. In order to be a viable lingua universalis, your language must in any case be capable of representing any (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Hyperclassical logic (aka independence-friendly logic) and its general significance.Jaakko Hintikka - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):404-423.
    Let us assume that you are entrusted by UNESCO with an important task. You are asked to devise a universal logical language, a Begriffsschrift in Frege's sense, which is to serve the purposes of science, business and everyday life. What requirements should such a “conceptual notation” satisfy? There are undoubtedly many relevant desiderata, but here I am focusing on one unmistakable one. In order to be a viable lingua universalis, your language must in any case be capable of representing any (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Partially ordered connectives and monadic monotone strict np.Lauri Hella, Merlijn Sevenster & Tero Tulenheimo - 2008 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 17 (3):323-344.
    Motivated by constraint satisfaction problems, Feder and Vardi (SIAM Journal of Computing, 28, 57–104, 1998) set out to search for fragments of satisfying the dichotomy property: every problem definable in is either in P or else NP-complete. Feder and Vardi considered in this connection two logics, strict NP (or SNP) and monadic, monotone, strict NP without inequalities (or MMSNP). The former consists of formulas of the form , where is a quantifier-free formula in a relational vocabulary; and the latter is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On elementary logics for quantitative dependencies.Miika Hannula, Minna Hirvonen & Juha Kontinen - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (10):103104.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relativized logspace and generalized quantifiers over finite ordered structures.Georg Gottlob - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):545-574.
    We here examine the expressive power of first order logic with generalized quantifiers over finite ordered structures. In particular, we address the following problem: Given a family Q of generalized quantifiers expressing a complexity class C, what is the expressive power of first order logic FO(Q) extended by the quantifiers in Q? From previously studied examples, one would expect that FO(Q) captures L C , i.e., logarithmic space relativized to an oracle in C. We show that this is not always (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Relativized logspace and generalized quantifiers over finite ordered structures.Georg Gottlob - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):545-574.
    We here examine the expressive power of first order logic with generalized quantifiers over finite ordered structures. In particular, we address the following problem: Given a familyQof generalized quantifiers expressing a complexity classC, what is the expressive power of first order logic FO(Q) extended by the quantifiers inQ? From previously studied examples, one would expect that FO(Q) capturesLC, i.e., logarithmic space relativized to an oracle inC. We show that this is not always true. However, after studying the problem from a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Lottery Semantics: A Compositional Semantics for Probabilistic First-Order Logic with Imperfect Information.Pietro Galliani & Allen L. Mann - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (2):293-322.
    We present a compositional semantics for first-order logic with imperfect information that is equivalent to Sevenster and Sandu’s equilibrium semantics (under which the truth value of a sentence in a finite model is equal to the minimax value of its semantic game). Our semantics is a generalization of an earlier semantics developed by the first author that was based on behavioral strategies, rather than mixed strategies.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • European Summer Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic, , Granada, Spain, 1987.H. -D. Ebbinghaus, J. Fernández-Prida, M. Garrido, D. Lascar & M. Rodriguez Artalejo - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (2):647-672.
  • Looking for structure in all the wrong places: Ramsey sentences, multiple realisability, and structure.Angelo Cei & Steven French - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (4):633-655.
    ‘Epistemic structural realism’ (ESR) insists that all that we know of the world is its structure, and that the ‘nature’ of the underlying elements remains hidden. With structure represented via Ramsey sentences, the question arises as to how ‘hidden natures’ might also be represented. If the Ramsey sentence describes a class of realisers for the relevant theory, one way of answering this question is through the notion of multiple realisability. We explore this answer in the context of the work of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Alternating (In)Dependence-Friendly Logic.Dylan Bellier, Massimo Benerecetti, Dario Della Monica & Fabio Mogavero - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (10):103315.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hintikka on the Foundations of Mathematics: IF Logic and Uniformity Concepts.André Bazzoni - 2015 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 44 (5):507-516.
    The initial goal of the present paper is to reveal a mistake committed by Hintikka in a recent paper on the foundations of mathematics. His claim that independence-friendly logic is the real logic of mathematics is supported in that article by an argument relying on uniformity concepts taken from real analysis. I show that the central point of his argument is a simple logical mistake. Second and more generally, I conclude, based on the previous remarks and on another standard fact (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On branching quantifiers in English.Jon Barwise - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):47 - 80.
  • Independence-friendly logic without Henkin quantification.Fausto Barbero, Lauri Hella & Raine Rönnholm - 2021 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 60 (5):547-597.
    We analyze the expressive resources of \ logic that do not stem from Henkin quantification. When one restricts attention to regular \ sentences, this amounts to the study of the fragment of \ logic which is individuated by the game-theoretical property of action recall. We prove that the fragment of prenex AR sentences can express all existential second-order properties. We then show that the same can be achieved in the non-prenex fragment of AR, by using “signalling by disjunction” instead of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Complexity of syntactical tree fragments of Independence-Friendly logic.Fausto Barbero - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (1):102859.
    A dichotomy result of Sevenster (2014) [29] completely classified the quantifier prefixes of regular Independence-Friendly (IF) logic according to the patterns of quantifier dependence they contain. On one hand, prefixes that contain “Henkin” or “signalling” patterns were shown to characterize fragments of IF logic that capture NP-complete problems; all the remaining prefixes were shown instead to be essentially first-order. In the present paper we develop the machinery which is needed in order to extend the results of Sevenster to non-prenex, regular (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cooperation in Games and Epistemic Readings of Independence-Friendly Sentences.Fausto Barbero - 2017 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 26 (3):221-260.
    In the literature on logics of imperfect information it is often stated, incorrectly, that the Game-Theoretical Semantics of Independence-Friendly quantifiers captures the idea that the players of semantical games are forced to make some moves without knowledge of the moves of other players. We survey here the alternative semantics for IF logic that have been suggested in order to enforce this “epistemic reading” of sentences. We introduce some new proposals, and a more general logical language which distinguishes between “independence from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Generalized Quantification as Substructural Logic.Natasha Alechina & Michiel Van Lambalgen - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (3):1006 - 1044.
    We show how sequent calculi for some generalized quantifiers can be obtained by generalizing the Herbrand approach to ordinary first order proof theory. Typical of the Herbrand approach, as compared to plain sequent calculus, is increased control over relations of dependence between variables. In the case of generalized quantifiers, explicit attention to relations of dependence becomes indispensible for setting up proof systems. It is shown that this can be done by turning variables into structured objects, governed by various types of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint.Gila Sher - 1991 - MIT Press.
    The Bounds of Logic presents a new philosophical theory of the scope and nature of logic based on critical analysis of the principles underlying modern Tarskian logic and inspired by mathematical and linguistic development. Extracting central philosophical ideas from Tarski’s early work in semantics, Sher questions whether these are fully realized by the standard first-order system. The answer lays the foundation for a new, broader conception of logic. By generally characterizing logical terms, Sher establishes a fundamental result in semantics. Her (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics.Alexandru Baltag & Sonja Smets (eds.) - 2014 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer International Publishing.
    This book illustrates the program of Logical-Informational Dynamics. Rational agents exploit the information available in the world in delicate ways, adopt a wide range of epistemic attitudes, and in that process, constantly change the world itself. Logical-Informational Dynamics is about logical systems putting such activities at center stage, focusing on the events by which we acquire information and change attitudes. Its contributions show many current logics of information and change at work, often in multi-agent settings where social behavior is essential, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hilbert's Metamathematical Problems and Their Solutions.Besim Karakadilar - 2008 - Dissertation, Boston University
    This dissertation examines several of the problems that Hilbert discovered in the foundations of mathematics, from a metalogical perspective. The problems manifest themselves in four different aspects of Hilbert’s views: (i) Hilbert’s axiomatic approach to the foundations of mathematics; (ii) His response to criticisms of set theory; (iii) His response to intuitionist criticisms of classical mathematics; (iv) Hilbert’s contribution to the specification of the role of logical inference in mathematical reasoning. This dissertation argues that Hilbert’s axiomatic approach was guided primarily (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Independence friendly logic.Tero Tulenheimo - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Generalized quantifiers.Dag Westerståhl - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Names.Sam Cumming - 2009 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • A Computational Learning Semantics for Inductive Empirical Knowledge.Kevin T. Kelly - 2014 - In Alexandru Baltag & Sonja Smets (eds.), Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics. Springer International Publishing. pp. 289-337.
    This chapter presents a new semantics for inductive empirical knowledge. The epistemic agent is represented concretely as a learner who processes new inputs through time and who forms new beliefs from those inputs by means of a concrete, computable learning program. The agent’s belief state is represented hyper-intensionally as a set of time-indexed sentences. Knowledge is interpreted as avoidance of error in the limit and as having converged to true belief from the present time onward. Familiar topics are re-examined within (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What kind of logic is “Independence Friendly” logic?Solomon Feferman - unknown
    1. Two kinds of logic. To a first approximation there are two main kinds of pursuit in logic. The first is the traditional one going back two millennia, concerned with characterizing the logically valid inferences. The second is the one that emerged most systematically only in the twentieth century, concerned with the semantics of logical operations. In the view of modern, model-theoretical eyes, the first requires the second, but not vice-versa. According to Tarski’s generally accepted account of logical consequence, inference (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations