Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Domain Extension and Ideal Elements in Mathematics†.Anna Bellomo - 2021 - Philosophia Mathematica 29 (3):366-391.
    Domain extension in mathematics occurs whenever a given mathematical domain is augmented so as to include new elements. Manders argues that the advantages of important cases of domain extension are captured by the model-theoretic notions of existential closure and model completion. In the specific case of domain extension via ideal elements, I argue, Manders’s proposed explanation does not suffice. I then develop and formalize a different approach to domain extension based on Dedekind’s Habilitationsrede, to which Manders’s account is compared. I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Pasch's empiricism as methodological structuralism.Dirk Schlimm - 2020 - In Erich H. Reck & Georg Schiemer (eds.), The Pre-History of Mathematical Structuralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 80-105.
  • The caesar problem in its historical context: Mathematical background.Jamie Tappenden - 2005 - Dialectica 59 (2):237–264.
    The issues surrounding the Caesar problem are assumed to be inert as far as ongoing mathematics is concerned. This paper aims to correct this impression by spelling out the ways that, in their historical context, Frege's remarks would have had considerable resonance with work that other mathematicians such as Riemann and Dedekind were doing. The search for presentation‐independent characterizations of objects and global definitions was seen as bound up with fundamental methodological questions in complex analysis and number theory.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Caesar Problem in its Historical Context: Mathematical Background.Jamie Tappenden - 2005 - Dialectica 59 (2):237-264.
    The issues surrounding the Caesar problem are assumed to be inert as far as ongoing mathematics is concerned. This paper aims to correct this impression by spelling out the ways that, in their historical context, Frege's remarks would have had considerable resonance with work that other mathematicians such as Riemann and Dedekind were doing. The search for presentation‐independent characterizations of objects and global definitions was seen as bound up with fundamental methodological questions in complex analysis and number theory.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How discrete patterns emerge from algorithmic fine-tuning: A visual plea for kroneckerian finitism.Ivahn Smadja - 2009 - Topoi 29 (1):61-75.
    This paper sets out to adduce visual evidence for Kroneckerian finitism by making perspicuous some of the insights that buttress Kronecker’s conception of arithmetization as a process aiming at disclosing the arithmetical essence enshrined in analytical formulas, by spotting discrete patterns through algorithmic fine-tuning. In the light of a fairly tractable case study, it is argued that Kronecker’s main tenet in philosophy of mathematics is not so much an ontological as a methodological one, inasmuch as highly demanding requirements regarding mathematical (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unveröffentlichte algebraische Arbeiten Richard Dedekinds aus seiner Göttinger Zeit 1855–1858.Winfried Scharlau - 1982 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 27 (4):335-367.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How mathematical concepts get their bodies.Andrei Rodin - 2010 - Topoi 29 (1):53-60.
    When the traditional distinction between a mathematical concept and a mathematical intuition is tested against examples taken from the real history of mathematics one can observe the following interesting phenomena. First, there are multiple examples where concepts and intuitions do not well fit together; some of these examples can be described as “poorly conceptualised intuitions” while some others can be described as “poorly intuited concepts”. Second, the historical development of mathematics involves two kinds of corresponding processes: poorly conceptualised intuitions are (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the youthful writings of Louis J. Mordell on the Diophantine equation y2-k=x3\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$y^2-k=x^3$$\end{document}. [REVIEW]François Lê & Sébastien Gauthier - 2019 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 73 (5):427-468.
    This article examines the research of Louis J. Mordell on the Diophantine equation y2-k=x3\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$y^2-k=x^3$$\end{document} as it appeared in one of his first papers, published in 1914. After presenting a number of elements relating to Mordell’s mathematical youth and his (problematic) writing, we analyze the 1914 paper by following the three approaches he developed therein, respectively, based on the quadratic reciprocity law, on ideal numbers, and on binary cubic forms. This analysis allows (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • D'un point de vue rigoureux et parfaitement général : pratique des mathématiques rigoureuses chez Richard Dedekind.Emmylou Haffner - 2014 - Philosophia Scientiae 18 (1):131-156.
    Dans cet article, je considère la pratique et la conception de la ri­gueur chez Richard Dedekind qui se dégagent de l’étude d’une sélection de ses travaux les plus importants. Une analyse des mentions multiples de réquisits de rigueur dans les textes de Dedekind amène à constater qu’il lie très étroi­tement la rigueur à la généralité. La première partie de l’article donne à voir les liens serrés tissés par Dedekind entre généralité et rigueur, dans sa théorie des fonctions algébriques co-écrite avec (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • D’un point de vue rigoureux et parfaitement général : pratique des mathématiques rigoureuses chez Richard Dedekind.Emmylou Haffner - 2014 - Philosophia Scientiae 18:131-156.
    Dans cet article, je considère la pratique et la conception de la ri­gueur chez Richard Dedekind qui se dégagent de l’étude d’une sélection de ses travaux les plus importants. Une analyse des mentions multiples de réquisits de rigueur dans les textes de Dedekind amène à constater qu’il lie très étroi­tement la rigueur à la généralité. La première partie de l’article donne à voir les liens serrés tissés par Dedekind entre généralité et rigueur, dans sa théorie des fonctions algébriques co-écrite avec (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • D’un point de vue rigoureux et parfaitement général : pratique des mathématiques rigoureuses chez Richard Dedekind.Emmylou Haffner - 2014 - Philosophia Scientiae 18 (1):131-156.
    Dans cet article, je considère la pratique et la conception de la ri­gueur chez Richard Dedekind qui se dégagent de l’étude d’une sélection de ses travaux les plus importants. Une analyse des mentions multiples de réquisits de rigueur dans les textes de Dedekind amène à constater qu’il lie très étroi­tement la rigueur à la généralité. La première partie de l’article donne à voir les liens serrés tissés par Dedekind entre généralité et rigueur, dans sa théorie des fonctions algébriques co-écrite avec (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Traditional logic and the early history of sets, 1854-1908.José Ferreirós - 1996 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 50 (1):5-71.
  • Dedekinds „Bunte Bemerkungen“ zu Kroneckers „Grundzüge“.Harold Edwards, Olaf Neumann & Walter Purkert - 1982 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 27 (1):49-85.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Space of valuations.Thierry Coquand - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 (2-3):97-109.
    The general framework of this paper is a reformulation of Hilbert’s program using the theory of locales, also known as formal or point-free topology [P.T. Johnstone, Stone Spaces, in: Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics, vol. 3, 1982; Th. Coquand, G. Sambin, J. Smith, S. Valentini, Inductively generated formal topologies, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 124 71–106; G. Sambin, Intuitionistic formal spaces–a first communication, in: D. Skordev , Mathematical Logic and its Applications, Plenum, New York, 1987, pp. 187–204]. Formal topology presents a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reading Gauss in the Computer Age: On the U.S. Reception of Gauss’s Number Theoretical Work (1938–1989).Maarten Bullynck - 2009 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 63 (5):553-580.
    C.F Gauss’s computational work in number theory attracted renewed interest in the twentieth century due to, on the one hand, the edition of Gauss’s Werke, and, on the other hand, the birth of the digital electronic computer. The involvement of the U.S. American mathematicians Derrick Henry Lehmer and Daniel Shanks with Gauss’s work is analysed, especially their continuation of work on topics as arccotangents, factors of n2 + a2, composition of binary quadratic forms. In general, this strand in Gauss’s reception (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The concept of “character” in Dirichlet’s theorem on primes in an arithmetic progression.Jeremy Avigad & Rebecca Morris - 2014 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 68 (3):265-326.
    In 1837, Dirichlet proved that there are infinitely many primes in any arithmetic progression in which the terms do not all share a common factor. We survey implicit and explicit uses ofDirichlet characters in presentations of Dirichlet’s proof in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, with an eye toward understanding some of the pragmatic pressures that shaped the evolution of modern mathematical method.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Mathematical Method and Proof.Jeremy Avigad - 2006 - Synthese 153 (1):105-159.
    On a traditional view, the primary role of a mathematical proof is to warrant the truth of the resulting theorem. This view fails to explain why it is very often the case that a new proof of a theorem is deemed important. Three case studies from elementary arithmetic show, informally, that there are many criteria by which ordinary proofs are valued. I argue that at least some of these criteria depend on the methods of inference the proofs employ, and that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Mathematical concepts: Fruitfulness and naturalness.Jamie Tappenden - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford University Press. pp. 276--301.
  • Methodology and metaphysics in the development of Dedekind's theory of ideals.Jeremy Avigad - 2006 - In Jose Ferreiros Jeremy Gray (ed.), The architecture of modern mathematics.
    Philosophical concerns rarely force their way into the average mathematician’s workday. But, in extreme circumstances, fundamental questions can arise as to the legitimacy of a certain manner of proceeding, say, as to whether a particular object should be granted ontological status, or whether a certain conclusion is epistemologically warranted. There are then two distinct views as to the role that philosophy should play in such a situation. On the first view, the mathematician is called upon to turn to the counsel (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Dedekind's 1871 version of the theory of ideals.Jeremy Avigad - manuscript
    By the middle of the nineteenth century, it had become clear to mathematicians that the study of finite field extensions of the rational numbers is indispensable to number theory, even if one’s ultimate goal is to understand properties of diophantine expressions and equations in the ordinary integers. It can happen, however, that the “integers” in such extensions fail to satisfy unique factorization, a property that is central to reasoning about the ordinary integers. In 1844, Ernst Kummer observed that unique factorization (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Frege's mathematical setting.Mark Wilson - unknown
    This survey article describes Frege's celebrated foundational work against the context of other late nineteenth century approaches to introducing mathematically novel "extension elements" within both algebra and geometry.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations