Switch to: References

Citations of:

The mathematical experience

Boston: Birkhäuser. Edited by Reuben Hersh & Elena Marchisotto (1981)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Beauty Is Not All There Is to Aesthetics in Mathematics.R. S. D. Thomas - forthcoming - Philosophia Mathematica:nkw019.
    Aesthetics in philosophy of mathematics is too narrowly construed. Beauty is not the only feature in mathematics that is arguably aesthetic. While not the highest aesthetic value, being interesting is a sine qua non for publishability. Of the many ways to be interesting, being explanatory has recently been discussed. The motivational power of what is interesting is important for both directing research and stimulating education. The scientific satisfaction of curiosity and the artistic desire for beautiful results are complementary but both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mathematical models and reality: A constructivist perspective. [REVIEW]Christian Hennig - 2010 - Foundations of Science 15 (1):29-48.
    To explore the relation between mathematical models and reality, four different domains of reality are distinguished: observer-independent reality, personal reality, social reality and mathematical/formal reality. The concepts of personal and social reality are strongly inspired by constructivist ideas. Mathematical reality is social as well, but constructed as an autonomous system in order to make absolute agreement possible. The essential problem of mathematical modelling is that within mathematics there is agreement about ‘truth’, but the assignment of mathematics to informal reality is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism.Jared Warren - 2020 - New York, USA: Oxford University Press.
    What is the source of logical and mathematical truth? This book revitalizes conventionalism as an answer to this question. Conventionalism takes logical and mathematical truth to have their source in linguistic conventions. This was an extremely popular view in the early 20th century, but it was never worked out in detail and is now almost universally rejected in mainstream philosophical circles. Shadows of Syntax is the first book-length treatment and defense of a combined conventionalist theory of logic and mathematics. It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Minds beyond brains and algorithms.Jan M. Zytkow - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):691-692.
  • Texting ECHO on historical data.Jan M. Zytkow - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):489-490.
  • Nested realities and human consciousness: The paradoxical expression of evolutionary process.Paul C. Wohlmuth - 1988 - World Futures 25 (3):199-235.
  • Computability, consciousness, and algorithms.Robert Wilensky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):690-691.
  • Psychology, or sociology of science?N. E. Wetherick - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):489-489.
  • Penrose's grand unified mystery.David Waltz & James Pustejovsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):688-690.
  • Between Turing and quantum mechanics there is body to be found.Francisco J. Varela - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):687-688.
  • Mathematical naturalism: Origins, guises, and prospects. [REVIEW]Bart Van Kerkhove - 2006 - Foundations of Science 11 (1-2):5-39.
    During the first half of the twentieth century, mainstream answers to the foundational crisis, mainly triggered by Russell and Gödel, remained largely perfectibilist in nature. Along with a general naturalist wave in the philosophy of science, during the second half of that century, this idealist picture was finally challenged and traded in for more realist ones. Next to the necessary preliminaries, the present paper proposes a structured view of various philosophical accounts of mathematics indebted to this general idea, laying the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Helmholtz’s Vortex Motion: An Embodied View of Mathematics in the Heuristics of Fluid Mechanics.Alain Ulazia & Enetz Ezenarro - 2020 - Topoi 39 (4):949-961.
    Some viewpoints on the foundations of mathematics and its philosophy are more connected to scientific practice and its heuristics, mainly with the construction of physical theories and the search for the best explanations of physical phenomena by means of abduction or the solution of problems by the analytical method. Some researchers have introduced the importance of human cultural activities into the cognitive aspects of the mental processes of scientists, proposing an embodied approach in the bridge between mathematics and reality. Fluid (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modelling Mathematical Reasoning in Physics Education.Olaf Uhden, Ricardo Karam, Maurício Pietrocola & Gesche Pospiech - 2012 - Science & Education 21 (4):485-506.
  • Mathematics, science and ontology.Thomas Tymoczko - 1991 - Synthese 88 (2):201 - 228.
    According to quasi-empiricism, mathematics is very like a branch of natural science. But if mathematics is like a branch of science, and science studies real objects, then mathematics should study real objects. Thus a quasi-empirical account of mathematics must answer the old epistemological question: How is knowledge of abstract objects possible? This paper attempts to show how it is possible.The second section examines the problem as it was posed by Benacerraf in Mathematical Truth and the next section presents a way (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Exactly which emperor is Penrose talking about?John K. Tsotsos - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):686-687.
  • Ideas and processes in mathematics: A course on history and philosophy of mathematics.Charalampos Toumasis - 1993 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 12 (2):245-256.
    This paper describes an attempt to develop a program for teaching history and philosophy of mathematics to inservice mathematics teachers. I argue briefly for the view that philosophical positions and epistemological accounts related to mathematics have a significant influence and a powerful impact on the way mathematics is taught. But since philosophy of mathematics without history of mathematics does not exist, both philosophy and history of mathematics are necessary components of programs for the training of preservice as well as inservice (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Extending explanatory coherence.Paul Thagard - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):490-502.
  • Explanatory coherence (plus commentary).Paul Thagard - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):435-467.
    This target article presents a new computational theory of explanatory coherence that applies to the acceptance and rejection of scientific hypotheses as well as to reasoning in everyday life, The theory consists of seven principles that establish relations of local coherence between a hypothesis and other propositions. A hypothesis coheres with propositions that it explains, or that explain it, or that participate with it in explaining other propositions, or that offer analogous explanations. Propositions are incoherent with each other if they (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   226 citations  
  • The thinker dreams of being an emperor.M. M. Taylor - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):685-686.
  • Formal systems as physical objects: A physicalist account of mathematical truth.la´Szlo´ E. Szabo´ - 2003 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 17 (2):117-125.
    This article is a brief formulation of a radical thesis. We start with the formalist doctrine that mathematical objects have no meanings; we have marks and rules governing how these marks can be combined. That's all. Then I go further by arguing that the signs of a formal system of mathematics should be considered as physical objects, and the formal operations as physical processes. The rules of the formal operations are or can be expressed in terms of the laws of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Visualizing the emergent structure of children's mathematical argument.Dolores Strom, Vera Kemeny, Richard Lehrer & Ellice Forman - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (5):733-773.
    Mathematics educators suggest that students of all ages need to participate in productive forms of mathematical argument (NCTM, 2000). Accordingly, we developed two complementary frameworks for analyzing the emergence of mathematical argumentation in one second‐grade classroom. Children attempted to resolve contesting claims about the “space covered” by three different‐looking rectangles of equal area measure. Our first analysis renders the topology of the semantic structure of the classroom conversation as a directed graph. The graph affords clear “at a glance” visualization of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Role of Semantics in Legal Expert Systems and Legal Reasoning.Ronald K. Stamper - 1991 - Ratio Juris 4 (2):219-244.
    The consensus among legal philosophers is probably that rule-based legal expert systems leave much to be desired as aids in legal decision-making. Why? What can we do about it? A bureaucrat administering some set of complex rules will ascertain the facts and apply the rules to them in order to discover their consequences for the case in hand. This process of deductive reasoning is characteristically bureaucratic.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • And then a miracle happens….Keith E. Stanovich - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):684-685.
  • The pretender's new clothes.Tim Smithers - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):683-684.
  • Theory autonomy and future promise.Matti Sintonen - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):488-488.
  • ECHO and STAHL: On the theory of combustion.Herbert A. Simon - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):487-487.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Axioms in Mathematical Practice.Dirk Schlimm - 2013 - Philosophia Mathematica 21 (1):37-92.
    On the basis of a wide range of historical examples various features of axioms are discussed in relation to their use in mathematical practice. A very general framework for this discussion is provided, and it is argued that axioms can play many roles in mathematics and that viewing them as self-evident truths does not do justice to the ways in which mathematicians employ axioms. Possible origins of axioms and criteria for choosing axioms are also examined. The distinctions introduced aim at (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • What keeps cells in tissues behaving normally in the face of myriad mutations?Harry Rubin - 2006 - Bioessays 28 (5):515-524.
    The use of a reporter gene in transgenic mice indicates that there are many local mutations and large genomic rearrangements per somatic cell that accumulate with age at different rates per organ and without visible effects. Dissociation of the cells for monolayer culture brings out great heterogeneity of size and loss of function among cells that presumably reflect genetic and epigenetic differences among the cells, but are masked in organized tissue. The regulatory power of a mass of contiguous normal cells (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Problems with Fallibilism as a Philosophy of Mathematics Education.Stuart Rowlands, Ted Graham & John Berry - 2011 - Science & Education 20 (7-8):625-654.
  • Seeing truth or just seeming true?Adina Roskies - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):682-683.
  • Systematic, unconscious thought is the place to anchor quantum mechanics in the mind.Thomas Roeper - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):681-682.
  • Explanation, independence and realism in mathematics.Michael D. Resnik & David Kushner - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (2):141-158.
  • From Geometry to Geology: An Invitation to Mathematical Pluralism Through the Phenomenon of Independence.Jonas Reitz - 2017 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 34 (2):289-308.
    This paper explores how a pluralist view can arise in a natural way out of the day-to-day practice of modern set theory. By contrast, the widely accepted orthodox view is that there is an ultimate universe of sets V, and it is in this universe that mathematics takes place. From this view, the purpose of set theory is “learning the truth about V.” It has become apparent, however, that the phenomenon of independence—those questions left unresolved by the axioms—holds a central (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Measuring the plausibility of explanatory hypotheses.James A. Reggia - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):486-487.
  • Explanatory coherence in understanding persons, interactions, and relationships.Stephen J. Read & Lynn C. Miller - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):485-486.
  • A Critique of a Formalist-Mechanist Version of the Justification of Arguments in Mathematicians' Proof Practices.Yehuda Rav - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (3):291-320.
    In a recent article, Azzouni has argued in favor of a version of formalism according to which ordinary mathematical proofs indicate mechanically checkable derivations. This is taken to account for the quasi-universal agreement among mathematicians on the validity of their proofs. Here, the author subjects these claims to a critical examination, recalls the technical details about formalization and mechanical checking of proofs, and illustrates the main argument with aanalysis of examples. In the author's view, much of mathematical reasoning presents genuine (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • The emperor's old hat.Don Perlis - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):680-681.
  • The nonalgorithmic mind.Roger Penrose - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):692-705.
  • Precis of the emperor's new mind.Roger Penrose - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):643-705.
    The emperor's new mind (hereafter Emperor) is an attempt to put forward a scientific alternative to the viewpoint of according to which mental activity is merely the acting out of some algorithmic procedure. John Searle and other thinkers have likewise argued that mere calculation does not, of itself, evoke conscious mental attributes, such as understanding or intentionality, but they are still prepared to accept the action the brain, like that of any other physical object, could in principle be simulated by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • An examination of some metaphorical contexts for biologically motivated computing.R. C. Paton, H. S. Nwana, M. J. R. Shave & T. J. M. Bench-Capon - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2):505-525.
    Biologically motivated computing seeks to transfer ideas from the biosciences to computer science. In seeking to make transfers it is helpful to be able to appreciate the metaphors which people use. This is because metaphors provide the context through which analogies and similes are made and by which many scientific models are constructed. As such, it is important for any rapidly evolving domain of knowledge to have developments accounted for in these terms. This paper seeks to provide one overview of (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Probability and normativity.David Papineau - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):484-485.
  • Coherence and abduction.Paul O'Rorke - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):484-484.
  • Is the uncertainty of mathematics the real source of its intellectual charm?Christopher Ormell - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (1):125–133.
    Christopher Ormell; Is the Uncertainty of Mathematics the Real Source of Its Intellectual Charm?, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 27, Issue 1, 30 May.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Infinitesimal Knowledges.Rodney Nillsen - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (3):557-583.
    The notion of indivisibles and atoms arose in ancient Greece. The continuum—that is, the collection of points in a straight line segment, appeared to have paradoxical properties, arising from the ‘indivisibles’ that remain after a process of division has been carried out throughout the continuum. In the seventeenth century, Italian mathematicians were using new methods involving the notion of indivisibles, and the paradoxes of the continuum appeared in a new context. This cast doubt on the validity of the methods and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Steadfast intentions.Keith K. Niall - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):679-680.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Answer to Neil Postman's Technopoly.David K. Nartonis - 1993 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 13 (2):67-70.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The powers of machines and minds.Chris Mortensen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):678-679.
  • The world as representation: Schopenhauer's arguments for transcendental idealism.Douglas James McDermid - 2003 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (1):57 – 87.
    (2003). The World as Representation: Schopenhauer's Arguments for Transcendental Idealism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 11, No. 1, pp. 57-87.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Optimization and connectionism are two different things.Drew McDermott - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):483-484.
  • Computation and consciousness.Drew McDermott - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):676-678.