Switch to: References

Citations of:

How to make the punishment fit the crime

Ethics 93 (4):726-752 (1982)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Fairness-Based Defense of Non-Punitive Responses to Crime.Giorgia Brucato & Perica Jovchevski - 2024 - Diametros 21 (79):40-55.
    In this paper, we offer a defense of non-punitive measures as morally justified responses to crime within a framework of society as a fair system of cooperation among free and equal individuals. Our argument proceeds in three steps. First, we elaborate on the premises of our argument: we situate criminal acts within a model of society as a fair system of cooperation, identify the types of unfair disadvantages crimes bring about, and consider the social aim of the criminal justice system. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The failure of retributivism.Russ Shafer-Landau - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 82 (3):289 - 316.
  • Retributivism and desert.Russ Shafer-Landau - 2000 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 81 (2):189–214.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Davis, Unfair Advantage Theory, and Criminal Desert.Don E. Scheid - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (3/4):375 - 409.
  • Just deserts for recidivists.Michael Davis - 1985 - Criminal Justice Ethics 4 (2):29-50.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A sound retributive argument for the death penalty.Michael Davis - 2002 - Criminal Justice Ethics 21 (2):22-26.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Normative Theory of the Clean Hands Defense.Ori J. Herstein - 2011 - Legal Theory 17 (3):171-208.
    What is the clean hands defense (CHD) normatively about? Courts designate court integrity as the CHD's primary norm. Yet, while the CHD may at times further court integrity, it is not fully aligned with court integrity. In addition to occasionally instrumentally furthering certain goods (e.g., court legitimacy, judge integrity, deterrence), the CHD embodies two judicially undetected norms: retribution and tu quoque (“you too!”). Tu quoque captures the moral intuition that wrongdoers are in no position to blame, condemn, or make claims (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Enduring Pertinence of the Basic Principle of Retribution☆.Vincent Geeraets - 2021 - Ratio Juris 34 (4):293-314.
    Ratio Juris, Volume 34, Issue 4, Page 293-314, December 2021.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Enduring Pertinence of the Basic Principle of Retribution☆.Vincent Geeraets - 2021 - Ratio Juris 34 (4):293-314.
    Many philosophers and legal scholars believe that the principle of retribution can be employed as a basis for respecting the offender as a person and for imposing relatively soft sentences. This belief is inspired, at least to a certain extent, by the penal philosophy of Kant and Hegel. My aim in this article is to question this widely held belief, with my contention being that retributivists locate the basis of these normative considerations in the wrong place. It is not the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Retributivism and Public Opinion: On the Context Sensitivity of Desert.Göran Duus-Otterström - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (1):125-142.
    Retributivism may seem wholly uninterested in the fit between penal policy and public opinion, but on one rendition of the theory, here called ‘popular retributivism,’ deserved punishments are constituted by the penal conventions of the community. This paper makes two claims against this view. First, the intuitive appeal of popular retributivism is undermined once we distinguish between context sensitivity and convention sensitivity about desert. Retributivism in general can freely accept context sensitivity without being committed to the stronger notion of convention (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mismeasuring “unfair advantage”: A response to Michael Davis. [REVIEW]David Dolinko - 1994 - Law and Philosophy 13 (4):493 - 524.
    One prominent contemporary retributivist theory is built on the notion that crime yields an “unfair advantage” over law-abiding citizens which punishment removes or nullifies. Michael Davis has defended this theory by constructing a market model of “unfair advantage” that he contends answers critics' objections to the retributivist enterprise. I seek to demonstrate the inadequacy of Davis's approach, arguing in particular that the market model rests on an incoherent notion of “demand” and would not, even if coherent, link “unfair advantage” to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What punishment for the murder of 10,000?Michael Davis - 2010 - Res Publica 16 (2):101-118.
    Those who commit crime on a grand scale, numbering their victims in the thousands, seem to pose a special problem both for consequentialist and for non-consequentialist theories of punishment, a problem the International Criminal Court makes practical. This paper argues that at least one non-consequentialist theory of punishment, the fairness theory, can provide a justification of punishment for great crimes. It does so by dividing the question into two parts, the one of proportion which it answers directly, and the other (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Punishment Theory’s Golden Half Century: A Survey of Developments from 1957 to 2007. [REVIEW]Michael Davis - 2009 - The Journal of Ethics 13 (1):73 - 100.
    This paper describes developments in punishment theory since the middle of the twentieth century. After the mid–1960s, what Stanley I. Benn called “preventive theories of punishment”—whether strictly utilitarian or more loosely consequentialist like his—entered a long and steep decline, beginning with the virtual disappearance of reform theory in the 1970s. Crowding out preventive theories were various alternatives generally (but, as I shall argue, misleadingly) categorized as “retributive”. These alternatives include both old theories (such as the education theory) resurrected after many (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Criminal desert and unfair advantage: What's the connection? [REVIEW]Michael Davis - 1993 - Law and Philosophy 12 (2):133 - 156.
  • Knowledge Problems and Proportionality.Daniel J. D'Amico - 2015 - Criminal Justice Ethics 34 (2):131-155.
    The proportionality standard demands a meaningful link between the severity of crimes and the punishments received for them. This article investigates the compatibility between this philosophical d...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conscience (rule) utilitarianism and the criminal law.R. B. Brandt - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (1):65 - 89.
    A rule- utilitarian appraisal of criminal law requires that the total system, including punishments, is justified only if it will expectably maximize public benefit, including its stigmatizing some behaviors as "offenses" and its prescribed punishment of these, such as imprisonment, with (possible) deterrent effects. In view of the paucity of evidence about the deterrent effect of prison sentences, some changes seem to be in order: reduction in the length of incarceration, replacement of prison by fines or restrictions on the convicted (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is There a Claim to Deserved Punishment?David Alm - 2014 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 52 (3):403-425.
    In this paper I defend the view that persons have a claim to deserved treatment, including many forms of punishment, against an objection resting on the principle that it is not possible to have a claim to harmful treatment. I do not challenge this principle, but argue, rather, that the harms wrongdoers typically deserve either (a) are not genuine harms at all (for reasons relevant to their being deserved) or (b) are not relevant to the content of these wrongdoers' claims.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Being Deserving.James Owen McLeod - 1995 - Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst
    The concept of desert is familiar to everyone. We have all heard that wrongdoers deserve punishment, that the virtuous deserve happiness, that hard workers deserve success, that innocent victims deserve compensation, that everyone deserves an adequate level of medical care, that no one deserves to be born handicapped, and so on. ;From these sayings, it is clear that desert is an evaluative concept. It therefore belongs to the class of concepts that includes rightness, justice, rationality, goodness, beauty, and others. Desert (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark