Switch to: References

Citations of:

A History of Indian Philosophy

Cambridge University Press (1922)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Nāgārjuna’s Catuṣkoṭi.Jan Westerhoff - 2006 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 34 (4):367-395.
    The catuṣkoṭi or tetralemma is an argumentative figure familiar to any reader of Buddhist philosophical literature. Roughly speaking it consists of the enumeration of four alternatives: that some propositions holds, that it fails to hold, that it both holds and fails to hold, that it neither holds nor fails to hold. The tetralemma also constitutes one of the more puzzling features of Buddhist philosophy as the use to which it is put in arguments is not immediately obvious and certainly not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • An Analysis of Consequentialism and Deontology in the Normative Ethics of the Bhagavadgītā.Sandeep Sreekumar - 2012 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 40 (3):277-315.
    This paper identifies the different normative ethical arguments stated and suggested by Arjuna and Krishna in the Gītā , analyzes those arguments, examines the interrelations between those arguments, and demonstrates that, contrary to a common view, both Arjuna and Krishna advance ethical theories of a broad consequentialist nature. It is shown that Krishna’s ethical theory, in particular, is a distinctive kind of rule-consequentialism that takes as intrinsically valuable the twin consequences of mokṣa and lokasaṃgraha . It is also argued that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Momentary consciousness and buddhist epistemology.Paul Schweizer - 1994 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (1):81-91.
  • From Vasubandhu to Śāntarak $$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}$$ ta.Edirivira R. Sarachchandra - 1976 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 4 (1-2):69-107.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolving perspectives on science and history: A chronicle of modern india's scientific enchantment and disenchantment (1850-1980).Dhruv Raina - 1997 - Social Epistemology 11 (1):3 – 24.
    This paper chronicles the cycles of scientism and romanticism that structure the discourse on science and technology in India since 1850. However, it does not promise a detailed review of this enormous archive. On the contrary, it aspires to identify the principle concerns, the important interlocutors, the prevalent frameworks and contextualizes them socio-politically, in both their local and global embodiments. In historical time, as has been suggested elsewhere, the scientism-romanticism dialectic acquires diversified formulations. This review suggests that in post-colonial India (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Time and change in sā [(m)\dot]\dot mkya-yoga.Hari Shankar Prasad - 1984 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 12 (1):35-49.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The conflict of voluntarism and dualism in the yogasūtra.Stephen H. Phillips - 1985 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (4):399-414.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the Alleged Indebtedness of the Vedānta Paribhāṣā Towards the Vedānta Kaumudī: Some Considerations on an Almost Forgotten Vivaraṇa Text.Gianni Pellegrini - 2016 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 44 (3):485-505.
    Dharmarāja Adhvarin’s Vedānta Paribhāṣā is a well-known introduction to Advaita Vedānta, targeted to beginners who are already trained in Navya Nyāya. According to Dasgupta, the VP is so heavily indebted to Rāmādvaya’s Vedānta Kaumudī, which was composed in the middle of the 14th century and is today almost forgotten, that the VP’s “claim to originality vanishes”. The VK was, however, only edited in 1955 and then again in 1973. In the light of this improved textual basis, what is our judgement (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The experience called 'reason' in classical Sā $$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{M} $$ khya. [REVIEW]Rodney J. Parrott - 1985 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (3):235-264.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reconciling dualism and non-dualism: three arguments in Vijñānabhikṣu’s Bhedābheda Vedānta. [REVIEW]Andrew J. Nicholson - 2007 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 35 (4):371-403.
    The late 16th century Indian philosopher Vijñānabhikṣu is most well known today for his commentaries on Sāṃkhya and Yoga texts. However, the majority of his extant corpus belongs to the tradition of Bhedābheda (Difference and Non-Difference) Vedānta. This article elucidates three Vedāntic arguments from Vijñānabhikṣu’s voluminous commentary on the Brahma Sūtra, entitled Vijñānāmṛtabhāṣya (Commentary on the Nectar of Knowledge). The first section of the article explores the meaning of bhedābheda, showing that in Vijñānabhikṣu’s understanding, “difference and non-difference” does not entail (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Karma-Yoga: The Indian Model of Moral Development.Zubin R. Mulla & Venkat R. Krishnan - 2014 - Journal of Business Ethics 123 (2):339-351.
    A comprehensive model of moral development must encompass moral sensitivity, moral reasoning, moral motivation, and moral character. Western models of moral development have often failed to show validity outside the culture of their origin. We propose Karma-Yoga, the technique of intelligent action discussed in the Bhagawad Gita as an Indian model for moral development. Karma-Yoga is conceptualized as made up of three dimensions viz. duty-orientation, indifference to rewards, and equanimity. Based on survey results from 459 respondents from two large Indian (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Roots of Indian Materialism in Tantra and Pre-Classical Sāṃkhya.Sonali Bhatt Marwaha - 2013 - Asian Philosophy 23 (2):180-198.
    Materialism is considered to be an anathema to Indian philosophy. Despite this, Indian tradition boasts of a strong materialist trend predating the Vedas. This paper traces the proto-materialist ideas as found in the ancient Tantra and pre-classical or original Sāṃkhya. Representing the naturalistic trend in Indian philosophy, ancient Tantra identified the brain as the seat of human consciousness. The pre-classical Sāṃkhya considered matter as the primal non-intelligent or non-sentient first cause from which the universe was to evolve. It considers the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Śaṇkara on Action and Liberation.Roopen Majithia - 2007 - Asian Philosophy 17 (3):231-249.
    In this paper I attempt to understand the implications of a kara's claim that liberation is not an action. If liberation is not an action, how is it up to us and therefore our responsibility? What role do actions have in a life concerned with liberation? The key to understanding a kara's view, I suggest, requires broad reflection on his claim in his commentary on Brahma S tra I.1.4 that cessation of action in accordance with Vedic prohibition is not an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Appearance and reality: Misinterpreting a Kara.Michael Levine - 1995 - Asian Philosophy 5 (2):151 – 158.
    Abstract Betty claims that Sahkara's philosophy [and non?dualism generally] fails definitively at the point where he leaves the human experience??sin and suffering??unaccounted for?. It is because Sahkara sees sin and suffering as ultimately illusory that Betty claims he leaves sin and suffering unaccounted for. However, Betty misconstrues Sahkara's view in the worst way possible. It is precisely because Sahkara seeks to account for sin and suffering, to take it seriously and as significant?a genuine problem for life?that Sahkara constructs the particular (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Man — The creator.Arnold Knust - 1976 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 4 (1-2):51-68.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ordinary nature: Pakati in the P li scripture.Knut A. Jacobsen - 1993 - Asian Philosophy 3 (2):75 – 87.
    Abstract This paper analyses the uses of the word ?nature? (in P?li pakati, Sanskrit prakrti) in the P?li scripture. In the P?li scripture pakati is never used as a concept of nature considered as a unity or an entity, or as a material cause, as in the S?mkhya and Yoga, but it describes acts which are considered natural, regular and usual. The article tries to answer three questions. 1. What is the meaning of the term pakati in the P?li scripture? (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Images of śaṃkara: Understanding the other. [REVIEW]Jacqueline Suthren Hirst - 2004 - International Journal of Hindu Studies 8 (1-3):157-181.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introduction.John Stratton Hawley - 2007 - International Journal of Hindu Studies 11 (3):209-225.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • No Black Scorpion is Falling: An Onto-Epistemic Analysis of Absence. [REVIEW]Nirmalya Guha - 2013 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (2):111-131.
    An absence and its locus are the same ontological entity. But the cognition of the absence is different from the cognition of the locus. The cognitive difference is caused by a query followed by a cognitive process of introspection. The moment one perceptually knows y that contains only one thing, z, one is in a position to conclude that y contains the absence of any non-z. After having a query as to whether y has x one revisits one’s knowledge of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On Arthāpatti.Nirmalya Guha - 2016 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 44 (4):757-776.
    Arthāpatti does not depend on observation of pervasion or background belief. It is certain in the sense that when S cognizes P through postulation, no other epistemic instrument would invalidate P. The Naiyāyika tries to reduce postulation to anumāna and/or tarka. I shall argue that it is neither. Due to its explanatory role, one may think that postulation plays an essential role in lakṣaṇā or indication. But this too is a misconception. Both tarka and lakṣaṇā depend on observation and background (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Raising “Authentic” Indian Children in the United States: Dynamism in the Ethnotheories of Immigrant Hindu Parents.Hemalatha Ganapathy-Coleman - 2013 - Ethos: Journal of the Society for Psychological Anthropology 41 (4):360-386.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Māyā and the pluralist predicament.Peter Forrest - 1995 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73 (1):31-48.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Going or knowing? The development of the idea of living liberation in the upani $$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}$$ ads. [REVIEW]Andrew O. Fort - 1994 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (4):379-390.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Substantivalism vs Relationalism About Space in Classical Physics.Shamik Dasgupta - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (9):601-624.
    Substantivalism is the view that space exists in addition to any material bodies situated within it. Relationalism is the opposing view that there is no such thing as space; there are just material bodies, spatially related to one another. This paper assesses this issue in the context of classical physics. It starts by describing the bucket argument for substantivalism. It then turns to anti-substantivalist arguments, including Leibniz's classic arguments and their contemporary reincarnation under the guise of ‘symmetry’. It argues that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • What the Cārvākas Originally Meant: More on the Commentators on the Cārvākasūtra.Ramkrishna Bhattacharya - 2010 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 38 (6):529-542.
    This essay proposes to review the problems of reconstructing and interpreting ancient texts, particularly philosophical commentaries, in the context of the Cārvāka/Lokāyata system of India. Following an overview of the Indian philosophical text tradition and the ontological and epistemological positions of the Cārvākas, three cases are discussed: (1) when there is no invariance in the text and the commentary, (2) when commentators differ among themselves in their interpretations, and (3) when contradictory interpretations are offered. The paper further discusses why certain (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Verses Attributed to Bṛhaspati in the Sarvadarśanasaṃgraha: A Critical Appraisal.Ramkrishna Bhattacharya - 2013 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (6):615-630.
    Sāyaṇa-Mādhava closed his exposition of the Cārvāka philosophy in his Sarva-darśana-saṃgraha, Chap. 1 by quoting 11 and a half verses, the authorship of all of which was attributed to Bṛhaspati, the eponymous founder of materialism in India. One of these verses is presumably taken from the Viṣṇupurāṇa. However, it is not Bṛhaspati but some demons, deluded by a Jain and a Buddhist monk, who say this. Bṛhaspati does not appear at all in this Purāṇa. Variant versions of the same story (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Svabhāvavāda and the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Historical Overview. [REVIEW]Ramkrishna Bhattacharya - 2012 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 40 (6):593-614.
    svabhāva (own being) and yadṛchhā (chance, accident) are named as two different claimants among others as the first cause (jagatkāraṇa) in the ŚvUp. But in later works, such as Aśvaghoṣa’s poems, svabhāva is synonymous with yadṛchhā and entails a passive attitude to life. Later still, svabhāva is said to be inhering in the Lokāyata materialist system, although in which sense—cosmic order or accident—is not always clearly mentioned. Svabhāva is also a part of the Sāṃkhya doctrine and is mentioned in the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the Language of Navya-Nyāya: An Experiment with Precision through a Natural Language. [REVIEW]Kamaleswar Bhattacharya - 2006 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 34 (1-2):5-13.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Development of logic in india: Significance of 'the duologue between pāyāsi and kassapa'.Ramkrishna Bhattacharya - 2016 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 57 (133):177-187.
    ABSTRACT 'The Duologue of King/Governor Pāyāsi' has long been recognised as a source for the proto-materialism current at the time of the Buddha. What needs to be stressed is the significance of the text as a pointer to the development of Logic in India. Perception, which is an accepted method of experimental enquiry, and reasoning from analogy, which can lead at best to a probable conclusion - these two are the only means employed to settle the dispute concerning the existence (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quotations and Commentaries in Advaita Vedānta: Some Philological Notes on Bhartṛprapañca’s “Fragments”.Ivan Andrijanić - 2015 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 43 (2-3):257-276.
    The oldest preserved commentary on the Br̥hadāraṇyaka-Upaniṣad was composed by Śaṅkara. Sureśvara composed a sub-commentary on this commentary, while Ānandagiri composed commentaries both on Śaṅkara’s commentary and on Sureśvara’s sub-commentary. All these four books contain a number of passages from earlier works which are not preserved. Sureśvara and Ānandagiri attributed some of these passages to a commentator named Bhartr̥prapañca. The aim of this article is to present a philological method which will establish which of the passages might be paraphrases and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Yogasūtra 1.10, 1.21–23, and 2.9 in the Light of the Indo-Javanese Dharma Pātañjala. [REVIEW]Andrea Acri - 2012 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 40 (3):259-276.
    . Besides a philosophical exposition of the tenets of a form of Śaiva Siddhānta, the Dharma Pātañjala contains a long presentation of the yoga system that apparently follows the first three chapters of Patañjal’s Yogasūtra , either interweaving Sanskrit excerpts from an untraced versified version of the latter text with an Old Javanese commentary, or directly rendering into Old Javanese what appears to be an original Sanskrit commentary. Although the Old Javanese prose often bears a strong resemblance with the arrangement (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark