Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Von einem subjekt ausgesagt werden und an einem subjekt vorliegen: Zur semantik genereller terme in der aristotelischen kategorienschrift.Benedikt Strobel - 2009 - Phronesis 54 (1):40-75.
    According to the Greek Commentators in late antiquity, Aristotle's Categories is primarily concerned with simple expressions in so far as they signify things. But what is it for a simple expression to signify a thing? As for (non-empty) singular terms, it is safe to say that they denote things. But what about general terms? How do they signify things? The question is crucial to the theory of the Categories , since, as is argued in the first section of this paper, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Essentialism in the Categories.Gabriel Shapiro - 2023 - Phronesis 68 (3):326-369.
    According to the Categories, predicates can be ‘said of’ their subjects or they can be ‘present in’ their subjects. The said-of relation has received relatively little scholarly attention, and scholars disagree on the answers to four foundational questions about the relation. (i) What is it? (ii) Is it an essential relation? (iii) How is it related to predication? (iv) Is it primitive? I argue that A is said-of B just in case A is a formal part of B. On this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Categories and Aristotle's Ontology.Mohan Matthen - 1978 - Dialogue 17 (2):228-243.
    Much recent work on Aristotle's Categories assumes that there is an ontological theory presented in that work and tries to reconstruct it on the basis of the slender evidence in the book. I claim that this is misguided. Using a distinction made by G.E.L. Owen between theory and the "phaenomena", I argue that the Categories is mainly concerned with setting out the phenomena -- the intuitions that any ontology must explain. This thesis has consequences for the interpretation of Aristotle's ontological (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Accidental sameness in Aristotle.Frank A. Lewis - 1982 - Philosophical Studies 42 (1):1 - 36.
  • The Texture of Aristotle’s Ontology.Tyler Huismann - 2022 - Apeiron 55 (4):557-586.
    Typically, Aristotle’s notion of an accidental unity is explained using our concept of identity, but doing so is fraught and liable to mislead. I argue that we should explain accidental unities in terms of sameness: doing so not only shows a coherence among texts thought to be in tension with one another, it reconciles the two competing conceptions of accidental unities in a satisfying way. I conclude by answering several Boolean questions that naturally arise in response to the inclusion of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The man without properties.Boris Hennig - 2017 - Synthese 194 (6).
    Contemporary philosophical logic rests on a distinction between things and properties. Properties are thought to differ from things in that their proper expression is incomplete or unsaturated. In this paper, I will argue that Aristotle did not distinguish between things and properties in this way. I will show, first, that Aristotle’s essences are not properties, and that certain passages in Aristotle make sense only if we do not take accidents to be properties either. The notion of a property is thus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Owen, Aristotle, and the Third Man.Gail Fine - 1982 - Phronesis 27 (1):13-33.
  • Aristotle's phaedo.M. J. Cresswell - 1987 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (2):131 – 155.
  • Individuo e Individuale in Aristotele.Barbara Botter - 2010 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 4 (2).
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark