Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1693 citations  
  • Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology.Jerry A. Fodor - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):63-73.
    The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   668 citations  
  • Methodological solipsism: replies to commentators.J. A. Fodor - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):99-109.
    The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Methodological solipsism.Andrew Woodfield - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):98-99.
  • Searle's straw men.Yorick Wilks - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):344-345.
  • Computers, cognition and philosophy.Robert Wilensky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):449-450.
  • The thermostat and the philosophy professor.Donald O. Walter - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):449-449.
  • The explanatory need for mental representations in cognitive science.Barbara Von Eckardt - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (4):427-439.
    Ramsey (1997) argues that connectionist representations 'do not earn their explanatory keep'. The aim of this paper is to examine the argument Ramsey gives to support that conclusion. In doing so, I identify two kinds of explanatory need—need relative to a possible explanation and need relative to a true explanation and argue that internal representations are not needed for either connectionist or nonconnectionist possible explanations but that it is quite likely that they are needed for true explanations. However, to show (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Explanatory Need for Mental Representations in Cognitive Science.Barbara Von Eckardt - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (4):427-439.
    Ramsey (1997) argues that connectionist representations ‘do not earn their explanatory keep’. The aim of this paper is to examine the argument Ramsey gives to support that conclusion. In doing so, I identify two kinds of explanatory need—need relative to a possible explanation and need relative to a true explanation and argue that internal representations are not needed for either connectionist or non‐connectionist possible explanations but that it is quite likely that they are needed for true explanations. However, to show (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Paying the price for methodological solipsism.Stephen P. Stich - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):97-98.
  • Rule following and rule reduction.William E. Smythe - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):343-344.
  • Simulation games.William E. Smythe - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):448-449.
  • Computational processes, representations and propositional attitudes.J. J. C. Smart - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):97-97.
  • How to turn an information processor into an understander.Aaron Sloman & Monica Croucher - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):447-448.
  • On Cognitivism's explanations and limitations.Thomas W. Simon - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (2):249-250.
  • Pain Begins.Aviv Spector Shirtz - 2022 - Theoria 88 (4):765-781.
    Theoria, Volume 88, Issue 4, Page 765-781, August 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Methodological realism.Robert Shaw & M. T. Turvey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):94-97.
  • Two objections to methodological solipsism.John R. Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):93-94.
  • The Chinese room revisited.J. R. Searle - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):345-348.
  • Intrinsic intentionality.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):450-457.
  • Understanding Searle.Roger C. Schank - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):446-447.
  • Computer simulations and surrogative reasoning for the design of new robots.Viola Schiaffonati & Edoardo Datteri - 2023 - Synthese 202 (1):1-20.
    Computer simulations are widely used for surrogative reasoning in scientific research. They also play a crucial role in engineering, more specifically in the design of new robotic systems, yet the nature of this role has been little discussed so far in the philosophy of technology literature. The main claim made in this article is that the notion of surrogative reasoning is central to understanding how computer simulations can serve the purpose of designing new robots. More specifically, it is argued that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Various senses of “intentional system”.Kenneth M. Sayre - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):760.
  • Searle's demon and the brain simulator.Steven F. Savitt - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):342-343.
  • Understanding and integration.Jerry Samet - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):341-342.
  • Methodological behaviorism: a case for transparent texonomy.David M. Rosenthal - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):92-93.
  • Searle and the special powers of the brain.Richard Rorty - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):445-446.
  • Mysticism as a philosophy of artificial intelligence.Martin Ringle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):444-445.
  • The formal and the opaque.Georges Rey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):90-92.
  • Parallelism and Functionalism.William M. Ramsey - 1989 - Cognitive Science 13 (1):139-144.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Connectionism and three levels of nativism.William Ramsey & Stephen P. Stich - 1990 - Synthese 82 (2):177-205.
    Along with the increasing popularity of connectionist language models has come a number of provocative suggestions about the challenge these models present to Chomsky's arguments for nativism. The aim of this paper is to assess these claims. We begin by reconstructing Chomsky's argument from the poverty of the stimulus and arguing that it is best understood as three related arguments, with increasingly strong conclusions. Next, we provide a brief introduction to connectionism and give a quick survey of recent efforts to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The behaviorist reply.Howard Rachlin - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):444-444.
  • Minds, pains, and performance.Howard Rachlin - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):341-341.
  • The ‘causal power’ of machines.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):442-444.
  • The chess room: further demythologizing of strong AI.Roland Puccetti - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):441-442.
  • Intentionality in the visual cortex?Roland Puccetti - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):758.
  • The Mind as Neural Software? Understanding Functionalism, Computationalism, and Computational Functionalism.Gualtiero Piccinini - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (2):269-311.
    Defending or attacking either functionalism or computationalism requires clarity on what they amount to and what evidence counts for or against them. My goal here is not to evaluate their plausibility. My goal is to formulate them and their relationship clearly enough that we can determine which type of evidence is relevant to them. I aim to dispel some sources of confusion that surround functionalism and computationalism, recruit recent philosophical work on mechanisms and computation to shed light on them, and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Computing mechanisms.Gualtiero Piccinini - 2007 - Philosophy of Science 74 (4):501-526.
    This paper offers an account of what it is for a physical system to be a computing mechanism—a system that performs computations. A computing mechanism is a mechanism whose function is to generate output strings from input strings and (possibly) internal states, in accordance with a general rule that applies to all relevant strings and depends on the input strings and (possibly) internal states for its application. This account is motivated by reasons endogenous to the philosophy of computing, namely, doing (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Causal dispositions + sensory experience = intentionality.Karl Pfeifer - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):757.
  • Foldor' solipsisms: dont's look a gift horse in the ….Donald A. Norman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):90-90.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The primary source of intentionality.Thomas Natsoulas - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):440-441.
  • Against neuroclassicism: On the perils of armchair neuroscience.Alex Morgan - 2022 - Mind and Language 37 (3):329-355.
    Neuroclassicism is the view that cognition is explained by “classical” computing mechanisms in the nervous system that exhibit a clear demarcation between processing machinery and read–write memory. The psychologist C. R. Gallistel has mounted a sophisticated defense of neuroclassicism by drawing from ethology and computability theory to argue that animal brains necessarily contain read–write memory mechanisms. This argument threatens to undermine the “connectionist” orthodoxy in contemporary neuroscience, which does not seem to recognize any such mechanisms. In this paper I argue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Does epistemology reduce to cognitive psychology?Richard Montgomery - 1989 - Philosophia 19 (2-3):245-263.
  • Decentralized minds.Marvin Minsky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):439-440.
  • Is the pen mightier than the computer?E. W. Menzel - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):438-439.
  • Minds, brains, programs, and persons.Drew McDermott - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):339-341.
  • Beliefs, machines, and theories.John McCarthy - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):435-435.
  • Intentionality: Hardware, not software.Grover Maxwell - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):437-438.
  • Artificial intelligence—the real thing?John C. Marshall - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):435-437.
  • The functionalist reply.William G. Lycan - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):434-435.