Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Orthomodular-valued models for quantum set theory.Masanao Ozawa - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):782-807.
    In 1981, Takeuti introduced quantum set theory by constructing a model of set theory based on quantum logic represented by the lattice of closed linear subspaces of a Hilbert space in a manner analogous to Boolean-valued models of set theory, and showed that appropriate counterparts of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice hold in the model. In this paper, we aim at unifying Takeuti’s model with Boolean-valued models by constructing models based on general complete orthomodular (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The development of mathematical logic from Russell to Tarski, 1900-1935.Paolo Mancosu, Richard Zach & Calixto Badesa - 2011 - In Leila Haaparanta (ed.), The development of modern logic. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The period from 1900 to 1935 was particularly fruitful and important for the development of logic and logical metatheory. This survey is organized along eight "itineraries" concentrating on historically and conceptually linked strands in this development. Itinerary I deals with the evolution of conceptions of axiomatics. Itinerary II centers on the logical work of Bertrand Russell. Itinerary III presents the development of set theory from Zermelo onward. Itinerary IV discusses the contributions of the algebra of logic tradition, in particular, Löwenheim (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Enciclopédia de Termos Lógico-Filosóficos.João Miguel Biscaia Branquinho, Desidério Murcho & Nelson Gonçalves Gomes (eds.) - 2006 - São Paulo, SP, Brasil: Martins Fontes.
    Esta enciclopédia abrange, de uma forma introdutória mas desejavelmente rigorosa, uma diversidade de conceitos, temas, problemas, argumentos e teorias localizados numa área relativamente recente de estudos, os quais tem sido habitual qualificar como «estudos lógico-filosóficos». De uma forma apropriadamente genérica, e apesar de o território teórico abrangido ser extenso e de contornos por vezes difusos, podemos dizer que na área se investiga um conjunto de questões fundamentais acerca da natureza da linguagem, da mente, da cognição e do raciocínio humanos, bem (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the impossibility of events of zero probability.Asad Zaman - 1987 - Theory and Decision 23 (2):157-159.
  • The Σ 2 1 theory of axioms of symmetry.Galen Weitkamp - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):727-734.
    The axiom of symmetry (A ℵ 0 ) asserts that for every function F: ω 2 → ω 2 there is a pair of reals x and y in ω 2 so that y is not in the countable set $\{(F(x))_n:n coded by F(x) and x is not in the set coded by F(y). A(Γ) denotes axiom A ℵ 0 with the restriction that graph(F) belongs to the pointclass Γ. In § 2 we prove A(Σ 1 1 ). In § (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Kuroda-style j-translation.Benno van den Berg - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (5):627-634.
    A nucleus is an operation on the collection of truth values which, like double negation in intuitionistic logic, is monotone, inflationary, idempotent and commutes with conjunction. Any nucleus determines a proof-theoretic translation of intuitionistic logic into itself by applying it to atomic formulas, disjunctions and existentially quantified subformulas, as in the Gödel–Gentzen negative translation. Here we show that there exists a similar translation of intuitionistic logic into itself which is more in the spirit of Kuroda’s negative translation. The key is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Relativization of Axioms of Strong Infinity to ^|^omega;1.Gaisi Takeuti - 1970 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 3 (5):191-204.
  • On ramsey’s theorem and the existence of infinite chains or infinite anti-chains in infinite posets.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2016 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 81 (1):384-394.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Primitive recursive ordinal functions with added constants.Stanley H. Stahl - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (1):77-82.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Outer models and genericity.M. C. Stanley - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (2):389-418.
  • Towards a unified framework for developing ethical and practical Turing tests.Balaji Srinivasan & Kushal Shah - 2019 - AI and Society 34 (1):145-152.
    Since Turing proposed the first test of intelligence, several modifications have been proposed with the aim of making Turing’s proposal more realistic and applicable in the search for artificial intelligence. In the modern context, it turns out that some of these definitions of intelligence and the corresponding tests merely measure computational power. Furthermore, in the framework of the original Turing test, for a system to prove itself to be intelligent, a certain amount of deceit is implicitly required which can have (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lattice initial segments of the hyperdegrees.Richard A. Shore & Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (1):103-130.
    We affirm a conjecture of Sacks [1972] by showing that every countable distributive lattice is isomorphic to an initial segment of the hyperdegrees, $\scr{D}_{h}$ . In fact, we prove that every sublattice of any hyperarithmetic lattice (and so, in particular, every countable, locally finite lattice) is isomorphic to an initial segment of $\scr{D}_{h}$ . Corollaries include the decidability of the two quantifier theory of $\scr{D}_{h}$ and the undecidability of its three quantifier theory. The key tool in the proof is a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Weak Forms of the Axiom of Choice and the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis.Arthur L. Rubin & Jean E. Rubin - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):7-22.
    In this paper we study some statements similar to the Partition Principle and the Trichotomy. We prove some relationships between these statements, the Axiom of Choice, and the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis. We also prove some independence results. MSC: 03E25, 03E50, 04A25, 04A50.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Filosofía de las matemáticas, teoría de cardinales grandes y sus bases cognitivas.Wilfredo Quezada - 2017 - Revista de Filosofía 73:281-297.
    En este artículo se examinan algunas implicaciones del naturalismo matemático de P. Maddy como una concepción filosófica que permite superar las dificultades del ficcionalismo y el realismo fisicalista en matemáticas. Aparte de esto, la mayor virtud de tal concepción parece ser que resuelve el problema que plantea para la aplicabilidad de la matemática el no asumir la tesis de indispensabilidad de Quine sin comprometerse con su holismo confirmacional. A continuación, sobre la base de dificultades intrínsecas al programa de Maddy, exploramos (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Generic embeddings.Jacob Manuel Plotkin - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (3):388-394.
  • Zermelo-Fraenkel consistency results by Fraenkel-Mostowski methods.David Pincus - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (4):721-743.
  • Cantorian set theory.Alex Oliver & Timothy Smiley - 2018 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 24 (4):393-451.
    Almost all set theorists pay at least lip service to Cantor’s definition of a set as a collection of many things into one whole; but empty and singleton sets do not fit with it. Adapting Dana Scott’s axiomatization of the cumulative theory of types, we present a ‘Cantorian’ system which excludes these anomalous sets. We investigate the consequences of their omission, examining their claim to a place on grounds of convenience, and asking whether their absence is an obstacle to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Great Philosophy: Discovery, Invention, and the Uses of Error.Christopher Norris - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (3):349-379.
    In this essay I consider what is meant by the description ‘great’ philosophy and then offer some broadly applicable criteria by which to assess candidate thinkers or works. On the one hand are philosophers in whose case the epithet, even if contested, is not grossly misconceived or merely the product of doctrinal adherence on the part of those who apply it. On the other are those – however gifted, acute, or technically adroit – to whom its application is inappropriate because (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Partially ordered interpretations.Nobuyoshi Motohashi - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (1):83-93.
  • Sets and supersets.Toby Meadows - 2016 - Synthese 193 (6):1875-1907.
    It is a commonplace of set theory to say that there is no set of all well-orderings nor a set of all sets. We are implored to accept this due to the threat of paradox and the ensuing descent into unintelligibility. In the absence of promising alternatives, we tend to take up a conservative stance and tow the line: there is no universe. In this paper, I am going to challenge this claim by taking seriously the idea that we can (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The roots of contemporary Platonism.Penelope Maddy - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1121-1144.
    Though many working mathematicians embrace a rough and ready form of Platonism, that venerable position has suffered a checkered philosophical career. Indeed the three schools of thought with which most of us began our official philosophizing about mathematics—Intuitionism, Formalism, and Logicism—all stand in fundamental disagreement with Platonism. Nevertheless, various versions of Platonistic thinking survive in contemporary philosophical circles. The aim of this paper is to describe these views, and, as my title suggests, to trace their roots.I'll begin with some preliminary (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Believing the axioms. I.Penelope Maddy - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):481-511.
  • Admissible ordinals and intrinsic consistency.Michael Machtey - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):389-400.
  • Talking About Models: The Inherent Constraints of Mathematics.Stathis Livadas - 2020 - Axiomathes 30 (1):13-36.
    In this article my primary intention is to engage in a discussion on the inherent constraints of models, taken as models of theories, that reaches beyond the epistemological level. Naturally the paper takes into account the ongoing debate between proponents of the syntactic and the semantic view of theories and that between proponents of the various versions of scientific realism, reaching down to the most fundamental, subjective level of discourse. In this approach, while allowing for a limited discussion of physical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Quantum Mechanics, Formalization and the Cosmological Constant Problem.Jerzy Król & Torsten Asselmeyer-Maluga - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (4):879-904.
    Based on formal arguments from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory we develop the environment for explaining and resolving certain fundamental problems in physics. By these formal tools we show that any quantum system defined by an infinite dimensional Hilbert space of states interferes with the spacetime structure M. M and the quantum system both gain additional degrees of freedom, given by models of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. In particular, M develops the ground state where classical gravity vanishes. Quantum mechanics distinguishes set-theoretic random forcing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Identity, indiscernibility, and philosophical claims.Décio Krause & Antonio Mariano Nogueira Coelho - 2005 - Axiomathes 15 (2):191-210.
    The concept of indiscernibility in a structure is analysed with the aim of emphasizing that in asserting that two objects are indiscernible, it is useful to consider these objects as members of (the domain of) a structure. A case for this usefulness is presented by examining the consequences of this view to the philosophical discussion on identity and indiscernibility in quantum theory.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Omitting types in set theory and arithmetic.Julia F. Knight - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (1):25-32.
  • Hanf numbers for omitting types over particular theories.Julia F. Knight - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (3):583-588.
  • Generic expansions of structures.Julia F. Knight - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (4):561-570.
  • The independence of Ramsey's theorem.E. M. Kleinberg - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2):205-206.
    In [3] F. P. Ramsey proved as a theorem of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF) with the Axiom of Choice (AC) the following result:(1) Theorem. Let A be an infinite class. For each integer n and partition {X, Y} of the size n subsets of A, there exists an infinite subclass of A all of whose size n subsets are contained in only one of X or Y.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Trees.Thomas J. Jech - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (1):1-14.
  • The axiom of choice for well-ordered families and for families of well- orderable sets.Paul Howard & Jean E. Rubin - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (4):1115-1117.
    We show that it is not possible to construct a Fraenkel-Mostowski model in which the axiom of choice for well-ordered families of sets and the axiom of choice for sets are both true, but the axiom of choice is false.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jumping through the transfinite: The master code hierarchy of Turing degrees.Harold T. Hodes - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (2):204-220.
    Where $\underline{a}$ is a Turing degree and ξ is an ordinal $ , the result of performing ξ jumps on $\underline{a},\underline{a}^{(\xi)}$ , is defined set-theoretically, using Jensen's fine-structure results. This operation appears to be the natural extension through $(\aleph_1)^{L^\underline{a}}$ of the ordinary jump operations. We describe this operation in more degree-theoretic terms, examine how much of it could be defined in degree-theoretic terms and compare it to the single jump operation.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Truth definitions, Skolem functions and axiomatic set theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):303-337.
    §1. The mission of axiomatic set theory. What is set theory needed for in the foundations of mathematics? Why cannot we transact whatever foundational business we have to transact in terms of our ordinary logic without resorting to set theory? There are many possible answers, but most of them are likely to be variations of the same theme. The core area of ordinary logic is by a fairly common consent the received first-order logic. Why cannot it take care of itself? (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The set-theoretic multiverse.Joel David Hamkins - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (3):416-449.
    The multiverse view in set theory, introduced and argued for in this article, is the view that there are many distinct concepts of set, each instantiated in a corresponding set-theoretic universe. The universe view, in contrast, asserts that there is an absolute background set concept, with a corresponding absolute set-theoretic universe in which every set-theoretic question has a definite answer. The multiverse position, I argue, explains our experience with the enormous range of set-theoretic possibilities, a phenomenon that challenges the universe (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Relations between some cardinals in the absence of the axiom of choice.Lorenz Halbeisen & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (2):237-261.
    If we assume the axiom of choice, then every two cardinal numbers are comparable, In the absence of the axiom of choice, this is no longer so. For a few cardinalities related to an arbitrary infinite set, we will give all the possible relationships between them, where possible means that the relationship is consistent with the axioms of set theory. Further we investigate the relationships between some other cardinal numbers in specific permutation models and give some results provable without using (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Elementary Extensions of Levy's Model of $A_{2}^{-}$.Wojciech Guzicki - 1974 - Synthese 27 (1):265-270.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Category theory, logic and formal linguistics: Some connections, old and new.Jean Gillibert & Christian Retoré - 2014 - Journal of Applied Logic 12 (1):1-13.
  • The generalized continuum hypothesis is equivalent to the generalized maximization principle.Joel I. Friedman - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (1):39-54.
    In spite of the work of Gödel and Cohen, which showed the undecidability of the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis from the axioms of set theory, the problem still remains to decide GCH on the basis of new axioms. It is almost 100 years since Cantor first conjectured the Continuum Hypothesis, yet we seem to be no closer to determining its truth. Nevertheless, it is a sound methodological principle that given any undecidable set-theoretical statement, we should search for “other axioms of set (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • One hundred and two problems in mathematical logic.Harvey Friedman - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (2):113-129.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Axioms of symmetry: Throwing darts at the real number line.Chris Freiling - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (1):190-200.
    We will give a simple philosophical "proof" of the negation of Cantor's continuum hypothesis (CH). (A formal proof for or against CH from the axioms of ZFC is impossible; see Cohen [1].) We will assume the axioms of ZFC together with intuitively clear axioms which are based on some intuition of Stuart Davidson and an old theorem of Sierpinski and are justified by the symmetry in a thought experiment throwing darts at the real number line. We will in fact show (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • An embedding of classical logic in S4.Melvin Fitting - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (4):529-534.
  • ω-circularity of Yablo's paradox.Ahmet Çevik - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1.
    In this paper, we strengthen Hardy’s [1995] and Ketland’s [2005] arguments on the issues surrounding the self-referential nature of Yablo’s paradox [1993]. We first begin by observing that Priest’s [1997] construction of the binary satisfaction relation in revealing a fixed point relies on impredicative definitions. We then show that Yablo’s paradox is ‘ω-circular’, based on ω-inconsistent theories, by arguing that the paradox is not self-referential in the classical sense but rather admits circularity at the least transfinite countable ordinal. Hence, we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Interpretation of the Zermelo‐Fraenkel Set Theory and the Kelley‐Morse Set Theory in a Positive Theory.Olivier Esser - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (3):369-377.
    An interesting positive theory is the GPK theory. The models of this theory include all hyperuniverses (see [5] for a definition of these ones). Here we add a form of the axiom of infinity and a new scheme to obtain GPK∞+. We show that in these conditions, we can interprete the Kelley‐Morse theory (KM) in GPK∞+ (Theorem 3.7). This needs a preliminary property which give an interpretation of the Zermelo‐Fraenkel set theory (ZF) in GPK∞+. We also see what happens in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Leibnizian models of set theory.Ali Enayat - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):775-789.
    A model is said to be Leibnizian if it has no pair of indiscernibles. Mycielski has shown that there is a first order axiom LM (the Leibniz-Mycielski axiom) such that for any completion T of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory ZF, T has a Leibnizian model if and only if T proves LM. Here we prove: THEOREM A. Every complete theory T extending ZF + LM has $2^{\aleph_{0}}$ nonisomorphic countable Leibnizian models. THEOREM B. If $\kappa$ is aprescribed definable infinite cardinal of a (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The positive properties of isolic integers.Erik Ellentuck - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (1):114-132.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A choice free theory of dedekind cardinals.Erik Ellentuck - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (1):70-84.
  • An algebraic difference between isols and cosimple isols.Erik Ellentuck - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):557-561.
    There is a fairly simple algebraic property that distinguishes isols from cosimple isols.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Remarks on Levy's reflection axiom.Martin Dowd - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):79-95.
    Adding higher types to set theory differs from adding inaccessible cardinals, in that higher type arguments apply to all sets rather than just ordinary ones. Levy's reflection axiom is justified, by considering the principle that we can pretend that the universe is a set, together with methods of Gaifman [8]. We reprove some results of Gaifman, and some facts about Levy's reflection axiom, including the fact that adding higher types yields no new theorems about sets. Some remarks on standard models (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gödel on Deduction.Kosta Došen & Miloš Adžić - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (1):31-51.
    This is an examination, a commentary, of links between some philosophical views ascribed to Gödel and general proof theory. In these views deduction is of central concern not only in predicate logic, but in set theory too, understood from an infinitistic ideal perspective. It is inquired whether this centrality of deduction could also be kept in the intensional logic of concepts whose building Gödel seems to have taken as the main task of logic for the future.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations