Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On Fork Arrow Logic and Its Expressive Power.Paulo A. S. Veloso, Renata P. De Freitas, Petrucio Viana, Mario Benevides & Sheila R. M. Veloso - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (5):489 - 509.
    We compare fork arrow logic, an extension of arrow logic, and its natural first-order counterpart (the correspondence language) and show that both have the same expressive power. Arrow logic is a modal logic for reasoning about arrow structures, its expressive power is limited to a bounded fragment of first-order logic. Fork arrow logic is obtained by adding to arrow logic the fork modality (related to parallelism and synchronization). As a result, fork arrow logic attains the expressive power of its first-order (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Congruences and ideals on Peirce algebras: a heterogeneous/homogeneous point of view.Sandra Marques Pinto & M. Teresa Oliveira-Martins - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (4-5):252-262.
    For a Peirce algebra \documentclass{article}\usepackage{amssymb}\begin{document}\pagestyle{empty}${\mathcal P}$\end{document}, lattices \documentclass{article}\usepackage{amssymb}\begin{document}\pagestyle{empty}$\mathrm{Cong}\mathcal {P}$\end{document} of all heterogenous Peirce congruences and \documentclass{article}\usepackage{amssymb}\begin{document}\pagestyle{empty}$\mathrm{Ide}\mathcal {P}$\end{document} of all heterogenous Peirce ideals are presented. The notions of kernel of a Peirce congruence and the congruence induced by a Peirce ideal are introduced to describe an isomorphism between \documentclass{article}\usepackage{amssymb}\begin{document}\pagestyle{empty}$\mathrm{Cong}\mathcal {P}$\end{document} and \documentclass{article}\usepackage{amssymb}\begin{document}\pagestyle{empty}$\mathrm{Ide}\mathcal {P}$\end{document}. This isomorphism leads us to conclude that the class of the Peirce algebras is ideal determined. Opposed to Boolean modules case, each part of a Peirce ideal I = (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Congruences and ideals on Boolean modules: a heterogeneous point of view.Sandra Marques Pinto & M. Teresa Oliveira-Martins - 2011 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 57 (6):571-581.
    Definitions for heterogeneous congruences and heterogeneous ideals on a Boolean module equation image are given and the respective lattices equation image and equation image are presented. A characterization of the simple bijective Boolean modules is achieved differing from that given by Brink in a homogeneous approach. We construct the smallest and the greatest modular congruence having the same Boolean part. The same is established for modular ideals. The notions of kernel of a modular congruence and the congruence induced by a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Augustus De Morgan and the Logic of Relations.Daniel D. Merrill - 1990 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    The middle years of the nineteenth century saw two crucial develop ments in the history of modern logic: George Boole's algebraic treat ment of logic and Augustus De Morgan's formulation of the logic of relations. The former episode has been studied extensively; the latter, hardly at all. This is a pity, for the most central feature of modern logic may well be its ability to handle relational inferences. De Morgan was the first person to work out an extensive logic of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A sequent calculus for relation algebras.Roger Maddux - 1983 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 25 (1):73-101.
  • Weak representations of relation algebras and relational bases.Robin Hirsch, Ian Hodkinson & Roger D. Maddux - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (3):870 - 882.
    It is known that for all finite n ≥ 5, there are relation algebras with n-dimensional relational bases but no weak representations. We prove that conversely, there are finite weakly representable relation algebras with no n-dimensional relational bases. In symbols: neither of the classes RA n and wRRA contains the other.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Finite methods in 1-order formalisms.L. Gordeev - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 113 (1-3):121-151.
    Familiar proof theoretical and especially automated deduction methods sometimes accept infinity where, in fact, it can be omitted. Our first example deals with the infinite supply of individual variables admitted in 1-order deductions, the second one deals with infinite-branching rules in sequent calculi with number-theoretical induction. The contents of Section 1 summarize and extend basic ideas and results published elsewhere, whereas basic ideas and results of Section 2 are exposed for the first time in the present paper. We consider classical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A necessary relation algebra for mereotopology.Ivo DÜntsch, Gunther Schmidt & Michael Winter - 2001 - Studia Logica 69 (3):381 - 409.
    The standard model for mereotopological structures are Boolean subalgebras of the complete Boolean algebra of regular closed subsets of a nonempty connected regular T 0 topological space with an additional "contact relation" C defined by xCy x ØA (possibly) more general class of models is provided by the Region Connection Calculus (RCC) of Randell et al. We show that the basic operations of the relational calculus on a "contact relation" generate at least 25 relations in any model of the RCC, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Notions of density that imply representability in algebraic logic.Hajnal Andréka, Steven Givant, Szabolcs Mikulás, István Németi & András Simon - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 91 (2-3):93-190.
    Henkin and Tarski proved that an atomic cylindric algebra in which every atom is a rectangle must be representable . This theorem and its analogues for quasi-polyadic algebras with and without equality are formulated in Henkin, Monk and Tarski [13]. We introduce a natural and more general notion of rectangular density that can be applied to arbitrary cylindric and quasi-polyadic algebras, not just atomic ones. We then show that every rectangularly dense cylindric algebra is representable, and we extend this result (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Complexity of equations valid in algebras of relations part I: Strong non-finitizability.Hajnal Andréka - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 89 (2):149-209.
    We study algebras whose elements are relations, and the operations are natural “manipulations” of relations. This area goes back to 140 years ago to works of De Morgan, Peirce, Schröder . Well known examples of algebras of relations are the varieties RCAn of cylindric algebras of n-ary relations, RPEAn of polyadic equality algebras of n-ary relations, and RRA of binary relations with composition. We prove that any axiomatization, say E, of RCAn has to be very complex in the following sense: (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations