Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Justice for Children: Autonomy Development and the State.Harry Adams - 2008 - State University of New York Press.
  • Paternalism.Jack Lively - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 15:147-165.
    What I wish to do in this paper is to look at a part of John Stuart Mill's ‘one very simple principle’ for determining the limits of state intervention. This principle is, you will remember, that ‘the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant.’.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Autonomy and Paternalism.Robert Young - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 8:47-66.
    Paternalism has generally been thought of as forcible or coercive interference with a person's liberty of action which is justified because it will prevent harm to that person's welfare interests or the like. Opposition to paternalistic interference with adults, whether it involves the intervention of the state or another adult individual, has usually been based on a concern to preserve human autonomy or self-determination. More strictly it is opposition to so-called ‘strong’ paternalism - interventions to protect or benefit a person (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Autonomy and Paternalism.Robert Young - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (sup1):47-66.
    Paternalism has generally been thought of as forcible or coercive interference with a person's liberty of action which is justified because it will prevent harm to that person's welfare interests or the like. Opposition to paternalistic interference with adults, whether it involves the intervention of the state or another adult individual, has usually been based on a concern to preserve human autonomy or self-determination. More strictly it is opposition to so-called ‘strong’ paternalism - interventions to protect or benefit a person (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paternalism and Justification.James Woodward - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (sup1):67-89.
    Much recent discussion in moral philosophy has focused on the contrast between those moral theories which are consequentialist in structure and those moral theories which admit independent side constraints on the means which can be used to achieve various ends. In this essay I shall attempt to show that this contrast provides an illuminating framework against which to understand two conflicting strategies for justifying paternalistic interference. The first, consequentialist strategy takes paternalistic interference to be justified when it will protect or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paternalism and Subsequent Consent.Donald Van De Veer - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (4):631 - 642.
    Some philosophers believe that appeals to promoting or maximizing good consequences are a suspect way of attempting to justify coercive interference with another person's actions. Suppose that is true. If there is a presumption that individuals have a right not to be coercively interfered with, then, foregoing utilitarian type appeals, it would seem that the only way to justify coercive interference of a paternalistic sort would be to show that under certain conditions the presumption fails.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Paternalism and Subsequent Consent.Donald Van De Veer - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (4):631-642.
    Some philosophers believe that appeals to promoting or maximizing good consequences are a suspect way of attempting to justify coercive interference with another person's actions. Suppose that is true. If there is a presumption that individuals have a right not to be coercively interfered with, then, foregoing utilitarian type appeals, it would seem that the only way to justify coercive interference of a paternalistic sort would be to show that under certain conditions the presumption fails.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Occupational Safety and Paternalism: Machan Revisited.Earl W. Spurgin - 2006 - Journal of Business Ethics 63 (2):155-173.
    In 1987, Machan provided a libertarian case against the right to occupational safety. Since before Machan’s essay appeared, many business ethicists and legal scholars have given considerable attention to the overall position Machan endorses: the acceptance of employment at will and the rejection of employee rights. No one yet has given adequate attention, however, to the fact that Machan’s argument against the right to occupational safety actually stands or falls independently of his overall position on employee rights. His argument ultimately (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What Is So Wrong with Killing People?Robert Young - 1979 - Philosophy 54 (210):515-528.
    If killing another human being is morally wrong on at least some occasions, what precisely makes it wrong on those occasions? I have framed the question thus to indicate that I shall not be considering the view that killing another human being is always and everywhere morally wrong. I take it as read that there are at least some morally justifiable killings. Once it is clear what is wrong with killing on some occasions it should become possible to explain why (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Digital and Electronic Revolution in Social Work: Rethinking the Meaning of Ethical Practice.Frederic G. Reamer - 2013 - Ethics and Social Welfare 7 (1):2-19.
    The recent and dramatic emergence of digital and other electronic technology in social work?such as online counseling, video counseling, avatar therapy, and e-mail therapy?has tested and challenged the profession's longstanding and widely accepted perspectives on the nature of both clinical relationships and core ethics concepts. These developments have transformed key elements of social work practice and require critical examination of the meaning and application of relevant ethical concepts in diverse cultures. This article explores pertinent ethical implications related to social workers' (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Another Look at Paternalism.Peter Hobson - 1984 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 1 (2):293-304.
    ABSTRACT This paper attempts to provide some new insights into the problem of justifying paternalism. To begin with, there is a general analysis of the concept of paternalism which examines the conditions that must be present for it to occur. A distinction is then drawn between two contexts in which paternalism exists—first, where it applies to individuals or clearly specifiable groups and second, where it applies to society in general. Different approaches to justification are required in each case. It is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Paternalism.Jack Lively - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 15:147-165.
    What I wish to do in this paper is to look at a part of John Stuart Mill's ‘one very simple principle’ for determining the limits of state intervention. This principle is, you will remember, that ‘the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant.’.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Should public health respect autonomy?S. A. Hall - 1992 - Journal of Medical Ethics 18 (4):197-201.
    This paper suggests that public health, due to its community orientation, may be ignoring certain ethical principles--namely the rights of individuals and communities to self-determination. The expectation of individual rights as a member of a community is reviewed and the additional right of a community for self-determination is proposed. The influences on ethical evaluations by the legal and economic environments are suggested, using US examples. The conclusion argues that as the focus of health-care delivery changes, it will become more important (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Subsequent Consent and Blameworthiness.Jason Chen - 2020 - HEC Forum 32 (3):239-251.
    Informed consent is normally understood as something that a patient gives prior to a medical intervention that can render it morally permissible. Whether or not it must be given prior to the intervention is debated. Some have argued that subsequent consent—that is, consent given after a medical intervention—can also render an otherwise impermissible act permissible. If so, then a patient may give her consent to an intervention that has already been performed and thereby justify a physician’s act retroactively. The purpose (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Self-justifying paternalism.David Archard - 1993 - Journal of Value Inquiry 27 (3-4):341-352.
  • Paternalism and Justification.James Woodward - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 8:67.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark