Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Interpreting self-ascriptions.J. van Brakel - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):393-395.
  • Do children understand the mind by means of a simulation or a theory? Evidence from their understanding of inference.Ted Ruffman - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (4):388-414.
    Three experiments investigating children's understanding of inference as a source of knowledge and beliefs were used to determine whether children use a theory in understanding the mind. A child watched while a sweet was placed in a box whereas a doll was merely given a message about which sweet had been transferred. Children were asked to judge whether the doll knew the colour of the sweet in the box and what colour the do6 would think the sweet was. The main (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Two kinds of representational functionalism: Defusing the combinatorial explosion.Joel Pust - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):392-393.
    Alvin Goldman (1993) presents three arguments against the psychological plausibility of representational functionalism (RF) as a theory of how subjects self-ascribe mental predicates. Goldman appears to construe RF as an account of attitude type self-ascription. His “combinatorial explosion” argument, however, proves devastating only to an implausible construal of RF as an account of attitude content self-ascription.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Carruthers' marvelous magical mindreading machine.Charlie Lewis & Jeremy I. M. Carpendale - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (2):152-152.
    Carruthers presents an interesting analysis of confabulation and a clear attack on introspection. Yet his theory-based alternative is a mechanistic view of which neglects the fact that social understanding occurs within a network of social relationships. In particular, the role of language in his model is too simple.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Speaking of beliefs: Reporting or constituting mental entities?Werner Greve & Axel Buchner - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):391-392.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to understand beliefs.Alison Gopnik - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):398-400.
  • Epistemology, two types of functionalism, and first-person authority.Alvin I. Goldman - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):395-398.
    My target article did not attribute a pervasive ontological significance to phenomenology, so it escapes Bogdan's “epistemological illusion.” Pust correctly pinpoints an ambiguity between content-inclusive and content-exclusive forms of folk functionalism. Contrary to Fodor, however, only the former is plausible, and hence my third argument against functionalism remains a threat. Van Brakel's charity approach to first-person authority cannot deal with authority vis-a-vis sensations, and it has some extremely odd consequences.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How we know our conscious minds: Introspective access to conscious thoughts.Keith Frankish - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (2):145-146.
    Carruthers considers and rejects a mixed position according to which we have interpretative access to unconscious thoughts, but introspective access to conscious ones. I argue that this is too hasty. Given a two-level view of the mind, we can, and should, accept the mixed position, and we can do so without positing additional introspective mechanisms beyond those Carruthers already recognizes.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Constructing an understanding of mind: The development of children's social understanding within social interaction.Jeremy I. M. Carpendale & Charlie Lewis - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (1):79-96.
    Theories of children's developing understanding of mind tend to emphasize either individualistic processes of theory formation, maturation, or introspection, or the process of enculturation. However, such theories must be able to account for the accumulating evidence of the role of social interaction in the development of social understanding. We propose an alternative account, according to which the development of children's social understanding occurs within triadic interaction involving the child's experience of the world as well as communicative interaction with others about (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • The epistemological illusion.Radu J. Bogdan - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):390-391.
  • A Computational Constructivist Model as an Anticipatory Learning Mechanism for Coupled Agent–Environment Systems.F. S. Perotto - 2013 - Constructivist Foundations 9 (1):46-56.
    Context: The advent of a general artificial intelligence mechanism that learns like humans do would represent the realization of an old and major dream of science. It could be achieved by an artifact able to develop its own cognitive structures following constructivist principles. However, there is a large distance between the descriptions of the intelligence made by constructivist theories and the mechanisms that currently exist. Problem: The constructivist conception of intelligence is very powerful for explaining how cognitive development takes place. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation